22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 517<br />

until <strong>the</strong> moment <strong>of</strong> time to which <strong>the</strong>y refer. Even <strong>the</strong> Stoics spoke about alternative<br />

prospective possibilities which are not yet fixed at <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> known causes,<br />

but <strong>the</strong>y also regarded fate as an active potency which ultimately necessitates<br />

everything. In <strong>the</strong> Peripatetic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> diachronic modalities it is assumed that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are transient individual alternative possibilities, but those which will not be<br />

realized disappear. 27 When Boethius refers to chance, free choice, and possibility,<br />

which restrict <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> causal necessity, his examples include temporalized<br />

modal notions which refer to diachronic prospective possibilities at a given moment<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. 28 A temporally determinate prospective possibility may not be realized at<br />

<strong>the</strong> time to which it refers, in which case it ceases to be a possibility. Boethius did<br />

not develop a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> simultaneous synchronic possibilities which remain intact<br />

even when diachronic possibilities have vanished, insisting that only what is actual<br />

at a certain time is possible at that time with respect to that time.<br />

The model <strong>of</strong> diachronic modalities provided Boethius with a more satisfactory<br />

tool for qualifying <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present than <strong>the</strong> frequency interpretation<br />

did. Instead <strong>of</strong> arguing that when <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditionally necessary<br />

proposition is removed, <strong>the</strong> proposition itself is contingent, he could also remark<br />

that when <strong>the</strong> antecedent conditions <strong>of</strong> a temporally necessary state <strong>of</strong> affairs are<br />

considered, it may be realized that it was not necessary before it was actualized. 29<br />

(See also 2.3 below.)<br />

1.4 Divine Modalities<br />

While Boethius’s works formed <strong>the</strong> main source <strong>of</strong> knowledge about philosophical<br />

modal <strong>the</strong>ories for early medieval thinkers, Augustine’s doctrine <strong>of</strong> creation made<br />

<strong>the</strong>m aware <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ological discussion <strong>of</strong> possibility and necessity which was based<br />

on different ideas. Augustine argued that God simultaneously created <strong>the</strong> first<br />

things and <strong>the</strong> seminal reasons for later things out <strong>of</strong> nothing. The creation was<br />

based on an eternal free act <strong>of</strong> God’s perfectly good will, and took place through<br />

his omnipotence. In Augustine’s Trinitarian view, <strong>the</strong> Son is a perfect image <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Fa<strong>the</strong>r and, as <strong>the</strong> Word, <strong>the</strong> seat <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> finite beings which in a<br />

less perfect manner can imitate <strong>the</strong> highest being. The ideas refer to possible<br />

actualization in <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> mutability. In this sense <strong>the</strong> possibilities have an<br />

ontological foundation in God’s essence. 30 This became <strong>the</strong> dominating conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ological modal metaphysics until Duns Scotus departed from it. 31<br />

27 See R.W. Sharples, Alexander <strong>of</strong> Aphrodisias on Fate, text, translation and commentary<br />

(London: Duckworth, 1983); S. Bobzien, Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy (Oxford:<br />

Clarendon Press, 1998).<br />

28 See, e.g., In Periherm. I, 106.11-14; 120.9-16; II, 190.14-191.2; 197.20-198.3; 203.2-11; 207.18-<br />

25. 29In Periherm. II, 245.4-246.19. See also Thomas Aquinas, In Peri herm. I.15, 201; Albert<br />

<strong>the</strong> Great, Comm. in Periherm. I.5.6, 421; Siger <strong>of</strong> Brabant, De necessitate et contingentia<br />

causarum 32.4-18.<br />

30 S. Knuuttila, ‘Time and Creation in Augustine’ in E. Stump and N. Kretzmann (eds.), The<br />

Cambridge Companion to Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 2001), 103-115.<br />

31 Knuuttila 1993, 135-6.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!