22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Latin Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> to 1100 39<br />

1611), containing <strong>the</strong> whole set <strong>of</strong> monographs, seems (from a note it contains)<br />

to have this material from a collection <strong>of</strong> Boethius’s works put toge<strong>the</strong>r in Constantinople<br />

in <strong>the</strong> 520s [Van de Vyver, 1935, 131-2]. Whe<strong>the</strong>r (as most scholars<br />

believe) <strong>the</strong> exemplar was brought to Europe from Byzantium in <strong>the</strong> tenth century,<br />

or it was simply studied and copied for <strong>the</strong> first time in this period, this rediscovery<br />

would have an important effect on how logic was studied. With regard to<br />

syllogistic, both surviving manuscripts and library catalogues show that, after <strong>the</strong><br />

tenth century, <strong>the</strong>re was a turn from using Apuelian <strong>the</strong>ory (directly from his Peri<br />

Hermeneias, or indirectly from <strong>the</strong> encyclopaedias) to using Boethius’s treatises<br />

[Sullivan, 1967, 193-203]. The <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, now much more conveniently<br />

available in <strong>the</strong> On Topical differentiae than before through <strong>the</strong> commentary on<br />

Cicero and <strong>the</strong> encyclopaedic accounts, would become one <strong>of</strong> logicians’ main concerns<br />

by <strong>the</strong> twelfth century.<br />

The three outstanding logicians <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> period are also those in whom <strong>the</strong> new<br />

developments can be seen with especial clarity: tentatively in Notker <strong>of</strong> St Gall,<br />

more definitely in Gerbert <strong>of</strong> Aurillac and most obviously in Abbo <strong>of</strong> Fleury.<br />

4.1 Notker <strong>of</strong> St Gall<br />

St Gall had been an important centre for logic since <strong>the</strong> ninth century (see above,<br />

p. 36). Notker Labeo (c. 950–1022) continued this tradition, especially within his<br />

project <strong>of</strong> translating central school-texts into <strong>the</strong> vernacular, Old High German.<br />

Of <strong>the</strong> four works he chose to translate, two were logical — a mark <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prominence<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject in <strong>the</strong> curriculum, especially since <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two translations<br />

(Books I and II <strong>of</strong> Martianus Capella; Boethius’s Consolation) were general philosophical<br />

works ra<strong>the</strong>r than texts <strong>of</strong> a particular discipline. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> two texts<br />

were both Aristotle: <strong>the</strong> Categories and On Interpretation, and to <strong>the</strong> German<br />

version some Latin glosses, mainly based on Boethius’s commentaries, are added<br />

[Notker <strong>the</strong> German, 1972; 1975]. Notker is <strong>the</strong>refore, in this way, a pioneer <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

new Boethian logic.<br />

Yet <strong>the</strong> most sophisticated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> writings attributed to him, On Syllogisms<br />

[Piper, 1882, 597-622], is based closely on works known since <strong>the</strong> ninth century:<br />

Apuleius’s Periermenias for categorical syllogisms, and, for <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms,<br />

Boethius’s commentary on Cicero’s Topics and Martianus Capella. By<br />

basing himself ultimately on Cicero, Notker produces an account a little nearer<br />

<strong>the</strong> Stoics than he could have found in On Hypo<strong>the</strong>tical Syllogisms, had he known<br />

it — and he even copies [Notker, 1882, 610-11] from Martianus Capella (cf. p. 6)<br />

a presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modes using numbers. But his conception <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogisms is thoroughly Boethian, as his adopting Boethius’s deviant form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

third mode indicates. He even elaborates this third mode, because he thinks its<br />

major premiss can be formed by preposing a negation to a contradiction <strong>of</strong> all four<br />

forms:- (1) ‘If it is day, it is night’; (2) ‘If it is not day, it is not night’; (3) ‘If it is<br />

day, it is not light’; (4) ‘If it is not day, it is light.’ He has given some thought to<br />

how this mode ‘arises from <strong>the</strong> first two’:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!