22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 143<br />

via responses to objections against it, or via objections to competing <strong>the</strong>orems,<br />

<strong>the</strong> presupposition being that its content and purpose are already clear. The extreme<br />

case <strong>of</strong> this is <strong>the</strong> widespread use <strong>of</strong> counter-exemplification as a means <strong>of</strong><br />

assessing inferential forms. An example <strong>of</strong> a form is given, and <strong>the</strong>n juxtaposed<br />

with a series <strong>of</strong> proposed counter-examples (instantiae), <strong>the</strong> entire commentary<br />

on <strong>the</strong> form being essentially this list consisting <strong>of</strong> example and counter-examples<br />

[Iwakuma, 1987, p. 438], with little or no supporting commentary. The late twelfth<br />

century logicians drew on basically <strong>the</strong> same logical corpus as Abelard, with <strong>the</strong><br />

exception that in mid-century Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations was brought into<br />

currency. The instantiae technique was doubtless encouraged by resulting interest<br />

in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory behind fallacy identification; but relentless use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technique<br />

served to make <strong>the</strong> logical literature <strong>of</strong> this period all <strong>the</strong> more inaccessible to <strong>the</strong><br />

uninitiated.<br />

That said, <strong>the</strong> richness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> resulting debate is undeniable. Its genesis <strong>of</strong>ten lies<br />

in <strong>the</strong> reaction <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s rivals to controversial elements in his own philosophical<br />

views, <strong>the</strong> ensuing discussion sharpened by <strong>the</strong> involvement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> corresponding<br />

schools. An outstanding example is <strong>the</strong> debate arising from Abelard’s handling<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topics “from opposites” and “from immediates.” Abelard’s argument for<br />

rejecting <strong>the</strong>se as legitimate topics was adapted by Alberic to pose a problem for<br />

Abelard’s whole approach to <strong>the</strong> conditional.<br />

Alberic’s argument starts from any obvious and self-evident conditional, such<br />

as “If Socrates is a man, Socrates is an animal.” Here are <strong>the</strong> steps, as suggested<br />

in a text originating from Alberic’s school [de Rijk, 1967b, pp. 65 (35)–66 (4)],<br />

and reconstructed thus:<br />

(i) If Socrates is a man and not an animal, Socrates is not an animal<br />

(ii) If Socrates is not an animal, Socrates is not a man<br />

(iii) If Socrates is not a man, it is not <strong>the</strong> case that (Socrates is a man and not<br />

an animal)<br />

(iv) Therefore, if Socrates is a man and not an animal, it is not <strong>the</strong> case that<br />

(Socrates is a man and not an animal). 108<br />

(iv) follows from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r three propositions by two applications <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogism. So <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> this argument is unimpeachable. If <strong>the</strong> argument is to be<br />

shown unsound, one <strong>of</strong> its three premises must be shown to be false. But (i) is a<br />

tautology, self-evidently true by simplification. (ii) follows from <strong>the</strong> original, selfevident<br />

conditional by contraposition. And (iii) just contraposes “If Socrates is a<br />

man and an animal, Socrates is a man,” itself a tautology, self-evidently true by<br />

simplification. So (iv) evidently follows. One can start from any true conditional<br />

and derive from it, through parallel steps, a proposition having <strong>the</strong> same logical<br />

form as (iv).<br />

108 See [Martin, 1986, pp. 570–571], [Martin, 1987a, pp. 394–395], [Martin, 1987b, p. 433],<br />

[Martin, 1992, p. 122] and [Martin, 2004a, pp. 191–192].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!