22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 135<br />

suggests a way <strong>of</strong> understanding <strong>the</strong>m which poses an impediment to grasping <strong>the</strong><br />

truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter — which is, <strong>of</strong> course, that implication and disjunction are<br />

correlative with conjunction, as opposed to being kinds <strong>of</strong> conjunction. Abelard’s<br />

work on hypo<strong>the</strong>ticals manifests much nascent insight into propositional logic, but<br />

also some inherited confusion. He is able to make some useful observations about<br />

<strong>the</strong> conditional and disjunctive connectives, and how <strong>the</strong>y relate to <strong>the</strong> negative<br />

connective. But for this to be a discussion <strong>of</strong> propositional logic in <strong>the</strong> fullest sense<br />

<strong>the</strong>re needs to be some notion <strong>of</strong> a connective for conjunction as well. What <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is instead is a way <strong>of</strong> speaking which can only impede <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> such a<br />

notion.<br />

There is to be found here, none<strong>the</strong>less, a rich discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interrelationship<br />

<strong>of</strong> conditionals, disjunctions and negations, in which Abelard’s sensitivity to <strong>the</strong><br />

difference between wide-scope and narrow-scope negation plays an important role.<br />

Just as a categorical proposition can be negated as a single unit by application<br />

<strong>of</strong> wide-scope negation, so with a hypo<strong>the</strong>tical, which counts as affirmative even<br />

if one or o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> its clauses happens to be negated: “Whatever hypo<strong>the</strong>ticals<br />

are asserted — whe<strong>the</strong>r out <strong>of</strong> two affirmatives, such as this: ‘If it is a man it<br />

is an animal’; or out <strong>of</strong> two negatives, such as this: ‘If it is not an animal, it is<br />

not a man’; or out <strong>of</strong> an affirmative and a negative or vice versa, such as this:<br />

‘If it is night it is not day’ — <strong>the</strong>y all seem to assert an affirmative meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

entailment” [Abelard, 1970, p. 476 (8–15)]. The narrow-scope negation affecting<br />

only <strong>the</strong> consequent in “If it is a man it is not an animal” does not negate <strong>the</strong><br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>tical as a whole, which still affirmatively expresses a relation <strong>of</strong> following<br />

between antecedent and consequent. If <strong>the</strong> narrow-scope negation did do this <strong>the</strong>n<br />

one would not be able to say that a relation <strong>of</strong> following is being expressed here.<br />

Besides achieving insight into how a conditional is negated, Abelard also discusses<br />

at length how it is related to disjunction. He receives from <strong>the</strong> Boethian<br />

tradition <strong>the</strong> foundational insight that (∼ p∨q) is equipollent with (p ⊃ q): “If <strong>the</strong><br />

conjunctive is composed <strong>of</strong> two affirmatives, <strong>the</strong> disjunctive one<br />

will consist <strong>of</strong> a negative and an affirmative” [Abelard, 1970, p. 488 (29–31)]. 102<br />

This means that what he says about <strong>the</strong> disjunctive relation must be carefully<br />

aligned with what he has already said about <strong>the</strong> conditional relation. This is a<br />

good result to arrive at, <strong>of</strong> course, but it is complicated by his relevance approach<br />

to understanding implication.<br />

He argues against defining a disjunction truth-functionally, ei<strong>the</strong>r inclusively as<br />

meaning that at least one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disjuncts is true, or exclusively as meaning that<br />

only one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is true. 103 The problem with <strong>the</strong>se definitions is brought out in<br />

<strong>the</strong> example, “Ei<strong>the</strong>r I am an animal or I am an ass” [Abelard, 1970, p. 490 (24)].<br />

Note that this proposition is true on both definitions; one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disjuncts is true<br />

(“I am an animal”), and in fact only one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is true (since “I am an ass” is<br />

false). So taken ei<strong>the</strong>r inclusively or exclusively, <strong>the</strong> disjunction is true. Now by<br />

<strong>the</strong> above equipollence <strong>the</strong> disjunction can be re-written as this conditional: “If I<br />

102 Reading si for is in line 29.<br />

103 On this point see <strong>the</strong> brief commentary in [Kneale and Kneale, 1962, p. 222].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!