22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 145<br />

failing this requirement, giving grounds for considering it false [Anonymous, 1983,<br />

p. 26; Martin, 1987a, p. 397; Iwakuma, 2004, p. 326]. The Melidunenses, by<br />

contrast, emphasize <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> a true antecedent ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> a relevant one; <strong>the</strong>ir principle is that nothing follows from a falsehood<br />

[Martin, 1987a, p. 398; Iwakuma, 2004, p. 327]. The antecedent <strong>of</strong> (i), if taken<br />

as a free-standing proposition, asserts that Socrates is a man and not an animal,<br />

which cannot be true since all men are animals. So what <strong>the</strong> antecedent asserts is<br />

false, and <strong>the</strong> principle that nothing follows from a falsehood accordingly identifies<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole conditional as false. Both <strong>the</strong> Porretani and Melidunenses support<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir analyses by counter-examples to suggest how in o<strong>the</strong>r instances <strong>the</strong> practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> allowing irrelevant or false antecedents will lead to problematic results. In<br />

both cases we have genuine propositional logic being done, <strong>the</strong> search being for<br />

constraints on conditionals — ei<strong>the</strong>r involving relevance conditions or truth conditions<br />

— sufficient to demonstrate <strong>the</strong> falsity <strong>of</strong> (i). The constraints naturally<br />

have a very limiting effect on what is accepted as a true conditional.<br />

The response <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Parvipontani is <strong>the</strong> most forward-looking. They too deal<br />

in genuine propositional logic, but are not concerned to constrain it in <strong>the</strong>se ways<br />

— because <strong>the</strong>y consider Alberic’s argument acceptable as it stands, and feel no<br />

incentive to demonstrate <strong>the</strong> falsity <strong>of</strong> (i) or any o<strong>the</strong>r premise; nor do <strong>the</strong>y wish<br />

to question <strong>the</strong> argument’s soundness. They in fact accept <strong>the</strong> principle that<br />

from a contradiction any statement whatsoever follows, so <strong>the</strong> self-contradicting<br />

conclusion (iv), where a proposition entails its own denial, is simply a routine<br />

product <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> initial self-contradicting antecedent <strong>of</strong> (i): “Socrates is a man and<br />

is not an animal.” One adherent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> school states openly that “If Socrates is a<br />

man and Socrates is not a man, <strong>the</strong>n Socrates is a crab, and so on for single things,<br />

for example a rose, a lily and <strong>the</strong> rest” [de Rijk, 1967a, p. 290; Martin, 1987a,<br />

p. 398; Iwakuma, 2004, pp. 327–328]. The lesson, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, is that any<br />

conclusion follows from a contradiction. 109 While <strong>the</strong> Parvipontani never advance<br />

from this point to constructing a full propositional logic in <strong>the</strong> modern sense, it is<br />

clear that <strong>the</strong>y prefigure in <strong>the</strong>ir response to Alberic one <strong>of</strong> modern propositional<br />

logic’s most suggestive doctrines.<br />

109The result is motivated by this sort <strong>of</strong> argument [de Rijk, 1967a, p. 290; Martin, 1987a, p.<br />

398; Iwakuma, 2004, pp. 327–328]:<br />

(i) If Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man, <strong>the</strong>n Socrates is a man.<br />

(ii) If Socrates is a man, Socrates is a man or a stone.<br />

(iii) Therefore, if Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man, Socrates is a man or a stone.<br />

(iv) If Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man, <strong>the</strong>n Socrates is not a man.<br />

(v) Therefore, if Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man, <strong>the</strong>n Socrates is a stone.<br />

(iii) follows from (i) and (ii) by hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogism. The inference from (iii) and (iv) to (v) is<br />

more abbreviated. “Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man” implies both “Socrates is a man<br />

or a stone” and “Socrates is not a man”; <strong>the</strong>se two latter propositions toge<strong>the</strong>r imply “Socrates<br />

is a stone” (by disjunctive syllogism). Therefore “Socrates is a man and Socrates is not a man”<br />

implies “Socrates is a stone” — which is what (v) asserts. With <strong>the</strong> relevant substitutions, <strong>the</strong><br />

above argument can be made to derive any conclusion from any contradiction.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!