22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

114 Ian Wilks<br />

nal plus <strong>the</strong> three negations) proliferate. When parallel listings are compiled for<br />

impossibility and necessity <strong>the</strong> forms proliferate fur<strong>the</strong>r. (Note that <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

separate treatment <strong>of</strong> contingency, since Abelard erroneously takes this mode as<br />

identical with possibility [Abelard, 1958, p. 24 (2); Abelard, 2006, 12.41]). So,<br />

starting with <strong>the</strong> simple de re statement “All men can possibly run,” varying it<br />

by quantification, negation, and substitution <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r modes, we end up with a<br />

twenty-four-entry list which is essentially an expanded square <strong>of</strong> opposition for<br />

quantified modal statements [Abelard, 1958, pp. 25 (19) — 26 (7); Abelard, 2006,<br />

12.44]. 58 Modal statements de dicto do not proliferate quite so generously, given<br />

<strong>the</strong> restriction just noted, but likwise generate a series <strong>of</strong> forms. Abelard is content<br />

simply to present <strong>the</strong>se relationships, and has no fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ory to build<br />

upon <strong>the</strong>m. This absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical enhancement is also <strong>the</strong> case — and more<br />

surprisingly so — for <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r relations he observes between <strong>the</strong> de re and de<br />

sensu modalities <strong>the</strong>mselves. An affirmative possibility de sensu is said to imply<br />

<strong>the</strong> corresponding affirmative possibility de re, but not vice versa [Abelard, 1958,<br />

p. 29 (14–16); Abelard, 2006, 12.55]. By contrast, an affirmative impossibility<br />

(= a negative possibility) de re is said to imply <strong>the</strong> corresponding affirmative<br />

impossibility de sensu [Abelard, 1958, pp. 29 (25)–30 (3); Abelard, 2006, 12.56],<br />

presumably again not vice versa. But for necessity <strong>the</strong> implication goes both ways.<br />

An affirmative necessity de sensu both implies and is implied by <strong>the</strong> corresponding<br />

affirmative necessity de re [Abelard, 1958, pp. 32 (30)–33 (2); Abelard, 2006,<br />

12.64]. These suggestive principles are tested against various examples, but are<br />

not pursued for <strong>the</strong> fundamental insights <strong>the</strong>y might yield into <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

central modal concepts <strong>the</strong>mselves.<br />

These remarks concern Abelard’s account <strong>of</strong> simple modality. He also has an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> determinate modality, which arises from this much-controverted Aristotelian<br />

principle: “What is necessarily is when it is, and what is not necessarily<br />

is not when it is not” [Aristotle, 1963, p. 52 (19a23)]. Something which was or is<br />

<strong>the</strong> case can be viewed as an irrevocable historical fact, and in this sense gains a<br />

necessity just by virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> passage <strong>of</strong> time. This is determinate necessity. The<br />

corresponding notion <strong>of</strong> possibility will be similarly distinct from simple possibility<br />

as defined purely in terms <strong>of</strong> compatibility with nature.<br />

The phrasing <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s principle exhibits <strong>the</strong> standard way <strong>of</strong> expressing determinate<br />

modal statements: apply an adverbial while-clause (i.e., a dum-clause)<br />

to <strong>the</strong> modal proposition so as to specify its modal content. The purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

specification is to indicate an interval <strong>of</strong> time, and <strong>the</strong> modal content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

is <strong>the</strong>n understood with reference to this interval. So Abelard works with<br />

examples like “It is possible for Socrates to read while he sits” and “It is possible<br />

for Socrates to read while he reads” [Abelard, 1958, p. 36 (14–15); Abelard, 2006,<br />

12.73]. 59 The possibility in question (reading) is thus characterized as applying<br />

58 There is some question as to whe<strong>the</strong>r Abelard fully grasped <strong>the</strong> relationships inherent in a<br />

square <strong>of</strong> opposition for quantified modals. See [Knuuttila, 1998, p. 88], [Lagerlund, 2000, p. 37],<br />

and [Thom, 2003, p. 55]. On this point, Martin defends Abelard in [Martin, 2001, pp. 122–123].<br />

59 Notice <strong>the</strong> structural difference between <strong>the</strong> two forms. In <strong>the</strong> first <strong>the</strong> determining verb,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!