22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 131<br />

wall” fails <strong>the</strong> containment condition for entailment, even though it passes <strong>the</strong><br />

necessity test [Abelard, 1970, p. 346 (18–28)]. Abelard also argues that attempts<br />

to re-formulate <strong>the</strong> maximal proposition for this topic in such a way as to make<br />

it acceptable fail; <strong>the</strong>y fail because <strong>the</strong>y yield variants <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition which<br />

now fall under a different topic. One such variant is “Whatever wholly agrees with<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole, that is, according to its individual parts, agrees with each one <strong>of</strong> those<br />

parts”; but this variant licenses universal-particular inferences, not whole-part<br />

ones, and hence does not qualify as a topic “from an integral whole.” Abelard<br />

draws <strong>the</strong> same conclusion <strong>of</strong> “If anything is predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole it is also<br />

predicated to all <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> it taken toge<strong>the</strong>r” [Abelard, 1970, p. 344 (6–24)]. 93<br />

(iii) Under <strong>the</strong> topic “from an equal” Abelard accepts four maximal propositions<br />

for what he calls “equality <strong>of</strong> predication” (that is, co-extensionality): “Whatever<br />

one equal is predicated <strong>of</strong>, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is too”; “From whatever one equal is<br />

removed, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is too”; “Whatever is predicated <strong>of</strong> one equal is predicated <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r”; and “Whatever is removed from one equal is removed from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r”<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 349 (28–32)]. He also accepts two maximal propositions for<br />

what he calls “equality <strong>of</strong> inference,” where in this case what are called “equals”<br />

are a given conditional and its contrapositive: “When one equal is posited, <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r is too”; “When one equal is denied <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is too” [Abelard, 1970, p. 351<br />

(31-32)]. These latter two maximal propositions simply affirm <strong>the</strong> equivalence <strong>of</strong><br />

contrapositives. 94 (iv) Under <strong>the</strong> topic “from antecedent or consequent” Abelard<br />

considers <strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> various basic rules <strong>of</strong> propositional logic, such as “If <strong>the</strong><br />

antecedent is posited <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> consequent is posited” [Abelard, 1970, p. 365 (18)].<br />

While not denying <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se, he argues that <strong>the</strong>y are not genuine maximal<br />

propositions, and so should be re-expressed in terms <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r propositions which<br />

are. For example, <strong>the</strong> rule just cited has no explanatory power, he argues, because<br />

it does not actually prove <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> conditional; to apply <strong>the</strong> rule at all in a<br />

given case one already needs to accept one proposition as antecedent and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

as consequent — in which case one has already in effect accepted <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

conditional <strong>the</strong> rule is supposed to be justifying [Abelard, 1970, p. 365 (24–26)].<br />

What actually demonstrates <strong>the</strong> relation between antecedent and consequent, he<br />

says, is consideration <strong>of</strong> how species relates to genus; he <strong>the</strong>refore refers <strong>the</strong> reader<br />

to <strong>the</strong> topic “from species” [Abelard, p. 365 (27–28)]. By this sort <strong>of</strong> reasoning<br />

all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principles associated with <strong>the</strong> topic “from antecedent or consequent” are<br />

rejected as maximal propositions. 95<br />

The above gives <strong>the</strong> barest hint <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intricacy <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s argumentation in<br />

this section. 96 He takes up a long series <strong>of</strong> what we would call logical and semantic<br />

principles and accepts or rejects <strong>the</strong>se, sometimes after painstaking re-formulation,<br />

93The topic “from <strong>the</strong> integral whole” is discussed in [Martin, 2004a, pp. 188–189] and [Stump,<br />

1989, pp. 100–101].<br />

94The topic “from an equal” is discussed in [Stump, 1989, pp. 103-106].<br />

95The topic “from antecedent or consequent” is discussed in [Stump, 1989, pp. 106–107].<br />

96A summary <strong>of</strong> maximal principles is provided by de Rijk in [Abelard, 1970, pp. lxxxiii–<br />

lxxxix]. For a comment on <strong>the</strong> general organization <strong>of</strong> topical <strong>the</strong>ory into three divisions (intrinsic,<br />

extrinsic and mediate) see [Martin, 2004a, p. 198, note 65].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!