22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 461<br />

• every non-ultimate significate in a conjunctive way — confused distributive<br />

material supposition, for example with ‘Every man is a monosyllabic word’,<br />

meaning that every single occurrence <strong>of</strong> ‘man’ is monosyllabic (cf. [Marsilius<br />

<strong>of</strong> Inghen, 1983, 59]).<br />

Indeed, in <strong>the</strong>se divisions we see <strong>the</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> individual concepts, inscriptions<br />

and utterances as legitimate members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ontology (something that was<br />

already crucial for Buridan), and <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> talking about <strong>the</strong>m in a much<br />

more refined way. With <strong>the</strong>se divisions, we can attribute a certain property to<br />

one specific occurrence <strong>of</strong> a term, to some or even to all its occurrences; in o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

words, here we certainly have a conceptual predecessor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> important token-type<br />

distinction, which was to be fully developed only in <strong>the</strong> 20 th century.<br />

Marsilius’s reformulation (or, perhaps better put, improvement) <strong>of</strong> supposition<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory so as to attribute <strong>the</strong> so-called modes <strong>of</strong> personal supposition to material<br />

supposition as well seems to have become <strong>the</strong> standard practice in <strong>the</strong> 15 th century.<br />

It is symptomatic that Paul <strong>of</strong> Venice, in his very influential <strong>Logic</strong>a Parva [Paul<br />

<strong>of</strong> Venice, 1984, 147], also adopted <strong>the</strong>se distinctions <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> supposition for<br />

material supposition.<br />

2.1.4 Problems and solutions for <strong>the</strong> negation<br />

Both in Buridan’s treatise on supposition and in <strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> Ockham’s Summa<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>ae dedicated to supposition (<strong>the</strong> last chapters <strong>of</strong> Part I), one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main<br />

topics are <strong>the</strong> syntactic rules determining which mode <strong>of</strong> (personal) supposition<br />

a term has on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syncategorematic terms present in a proposition<br />

(quantifying terms such as ‘some’, ‘every’, negating terms etc.) and word order.<br />

We learn for example that an affirmative sign <strong>of</strong> universality (‘every’) causes <strong>the</strong><br />

term immediately following it to have confused and distributive supposition, and<br />

that it causes a term mediately (i.e. not immediately) following it to have merely<br />

confused supposition (so in ‘Every man is an animal’, <strong>the</strong> subject, which follows<br />

‘every’ immediately, has confused and distributive supposition, while <strong>the</strong> predicate,<br />

which follows ‘every’ mediately, has merely confused supposition). We also learn<br />

that a negative sign <strong>of</strong> universality (‘no’) causes all terms following it (immediately<br />

and mediately) to have confused and distributive supposition, and that when <strong>the</strong><br />

negation is placed relative to <strong>the</strong> copula (as in ‘A man is not a stone’), it causes<br />

<strong>the</strong> predicate to have confused and distributive supposition. As for determinate<br />

supposition, it occurs when a term immediately follows a sign <strong>of</strong> particularity<br />

(‘some’) or when it does not follow any syncategorematic term (as in ‘a man is an<br />

animal’).<br />

But matters become significantly more complicated once one departs from <strong>the</strong><br />

four traditional propositional forms (‘Every A is B’, ‘Some A is B’, ‘No A is B’and<br />

‘Some A is not B’), especially when iteration <strong>of</strong> syncategorematic terms occurs.<br />

As argued by Parsons in [Parsons, 1997] and in his piece in this volume, in <strong>the</strong> 14 th<br />

century it became current to classify <strong>the</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> personal supposition globally<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than locally, as had been done in <strong>the</strong> 13 th century — that is, taking into

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!