22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

584 Mikko Yrjönsuuri<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y were closely connected from <strong>the</strong> very beginning, and many later authors<br />

chose to present insolubles as obligational disputations in <strong>the</strong> technical sense.<br />

As <strong>the</strong>y were known in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, <strong>the</strong> technical<br />

obligational disputations consisted <strong>of</strong> encounters between an opponent and a respondent,<br />

with <strong>the</strong> opponent first assigning <strong>the</strong> respondent some special duty (obligatio),<br />

typically that <strong>of</strong> accepting a sentence known to be false, and <strong>the</strong>n putting<br />

forward sentences for <strong>the</strong> respondent to concede, deny or doubt in a consistent<br />

manner. The idea was that <strong>the</strong> respondent had to pay attention to inferential<br />

relationships between different sentences. In <strong>the</strong> standard form, <strong>the</strong> disputation<br />

would start with <strong>the</strong> opponent “positing” a sentence, or laying down as <strong>the</strong> basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasoning a false, perhaps impossible sentence, <strong>the</strong> positum as it was called. The<br />

respondent should accept <strong>the</strong> positum if he thought that it could be maintained<br />

consistently. Then he should answer o<strong>the</strong>r sentences so that he concedes consistently<br />

everything that logically follows from <strong>the</strong> presented positum. In a way, this<br />

technique served for <strong>the</strong> Latin medieval period as a paradigm <strong>of</strong> how one should<br />

deal with false assumptions in a disputational context. 3<br />

In <strong>the</strong> medieval manuscripts from thirteenth century onwards, treatises on insolubles<br />

were very <strong>of</strong>ten associated with treatises <strong>of</strong> obligational disputations. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<br />

paradoxical or at least complicated types <strong>of</strong> self-reference were <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

constructed in <strong>the</strong> obligations treatises. It seems that already <strong>the</strong> very earliest<br />

obligations treatises address issues that are <strong>of</strong> genuine relevance to <strong>the</strong> topics<br />

discussed in <strong>the</strong> treatises on insolubles. One such is <strong>the</strong> anonymous “Emmeran<br />

Treatise on False Positio”, which seems to date from <strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thirteenth<br />

century. 4<br />

The author <strong>of</strong> this text takes considerable effort to discuss exact rules for what<br />

<strong>the</strong> respondent should do if <strong>the</strong> opponent wishes to lay down as <strong>the</strong> positum something<br />

containing ‘a falsehood is posited’. As <strong>the</strong> text tells, <strong>the</strong> respondent ought<br />

not to accept this sentence as <strong>the</strong> positum, since “a contradiction would follow”.<br />

Interestingly, <strong>the</strong> author does not say that a contradiction would follow technically<br />

in <strong>the</strong> disputation, but outside it. As he says, <strong>the</strong> opponent would <strong>the</strong>n say “time<br />

is finished”, which in <strong>the</strong>se disputations means that one must turn into real discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth values and not care anymore about <strong>the</strong> duty to grant <strong>the</strong> positum<br />

and anything following from it [Anonymous, 2001, 199–200]. The idea is simple:<br />

when ‘a falsehood is posited’ is posited, it becomes a sentence that claims itself to<br />

be false. The resulting paradox is quite near <strong>the</strong> standard Liar.<br />

In ano<strong>the</strong>r interesting move <strong>the</strong> author considers ‘a falsehood is conceded’ as<br />

<strong>the</strong> positum. It can be accepted, as he points out, since no contradiction follows at<br />

this stage. The sentence is not paradoxical as a positum, because <strong>the</strong> response to<br />

<strong>the</strong> positum is not called ‘conceding’ but ‘accepting’. However, if it is posited and<br />

accepted, and <strong>the</strong> opponent puts it forward as a proposition, <strong>the</strong> respondent loses<br />

<strong>the</strong> disputation. The proposition put forward follows directly from <strong>the</strong> positum<br />

as a repetition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same sentence. Therefore, it should be conceded, but it<br />

3 For deeper discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genre, see, e.g. [Yrjönsuuri, 1994; 2001; Keffer, 2001].<br />

4 Edition in [De Rijk, 1974], translation [Anonymous, 2001].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!