22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 169<br />

Sherwood’s Equipollences: 13 Replacing a phrase below by ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

on <strong>the</strong> same line yields a logically equivalent proposition: 14<br />

every A no A not not some A not<br />

no A not some A every A not<br />

some A not no A not every A not<br />

some A not not no A not not every A<br />

An example is <strong>the</strong> equivalence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old form ‘No A is B’ with <strong>the</strong> new form<br />

‘Every A is not B’. It is also assumed that an unquantified predicate term ‘B’ is<br />

equivalent to <strong>the</strong> particular ‘some B’, so <strong>the</strong> old form ‘Some A is B’ is equivalent<br />

to ‘Some A is some B’, which is equipollent to ‘Some A is not no B’. Likewise,<br />

‘No A is every B’ is equivalent to ‘Every A is not every B’ andalsoto‘Every A<br />

someBisnot’.<br />

Notice that application <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se equipollences leaves an affirmative proposition<br />

affirmative, and a negative proposition negative. (Suppose that ‘no’ and<br />

‘not’ are (<strong>the</strong> only) negative signs. A proposition is affirmative if it contains no<br />

negative signs or an even number <strong>of</strong> negative signs; o<strong>the</strong>rwise it is negative.) They<br />

thus preserve <strong>the</strong> principle that affirmatives with empty main terms are false, and<br />

negatives with empty main terms are true.<br />

Suppose that we take Aristotle’s original list <strong>of</strong> four (non-singular; non-indefinite)<br />

categorical propositions and add <strong>the</strong> quantifier sign ‘every’ to <strong>the</strong> predicate. This<br />

gives us a list <strong>of</strong> eight forms:<br />

13This little chart is from William Sherwood I.19. In applications to categorical propositions<br />

<strong>the</strong> actual form would have <strong>the</strong> normal Latin word order ‘not is’ instead <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> English order ‘is<br />

not’. It is possible to be precise about what propositions are included in this stock <strong>of</strong> what I am<br />

calling basic categorical propositions. First, <strong>the</strong> following rules produce categorical propositions<br />

whose copula occurs at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition. (These are meaningful in Latin.):<br />

1. A denoting phrase consists <strong>of</strong> a quantifier sign (‘every’, ‘some’, ‘a(n)’ or ‘no’) followed by<br />

a common noun.<br />

2. ‘is’ is a partial categorical proposition<br />

3. If φ is a partial categorical proposition with zero or one denoting phrases in it, and if δ is<br />

a denoting phrase, <strong>the</strong>n δ followed by φ is a partial categorical proposition<br />

4. If φ is a partial categorical proposition, so is ‘not φ’.<br />

5. A categorical proposition is any partial categorical proposition with two denoting phrases.<br />

Examples: ‘is’ ⇒ ‘no donkey is’ ⇒ ‘some animal no donkey is’.<br />

‘is’ ⇒ ‘some donkey is’ ⇒ ‘not some donkey is’ ⇒ ‘an animal not some donkey is’<br />

To put <strong>the</strong> verb in its more natural order in <strong>the</strong> middle:<br />

If φ is a categorical proposition which ends with ‘is’, if <strong>the</strong>re is a denoting phrase<br />

immediately to its left, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y may be permuted<br />

Example: ‘some animal not no donkey is’ ⇒ ‘some animal not is no donkey’<br />

(For English readers, change <strong>the</strong> Latin word order ‘not is’ to ‘isn’t’: ⇒ ‘some animal isn’t no<br />

donkey.)<br />

14In Latin <strong>the</strong> negation naturally precedes <strong>the</strong> verb. For applying <strong>the</strong>se equipollences <strong>the</strong><br />

negation coming before <strong>the</strong> verb can be treated as if it came after, so that ‘No A not is some<br />

B’ can be treated as ‘No A is-not some B’ ≈ ‘No A is no B’. A similar provision applies to<br />

English, where negation follows <strong>the</strong> copula ‘is’.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!