22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 141<br />

compound conditional forms just considered, Abelard lists <strong>the</strong> mediate conditional<br />

forms [Abelard, 1970, pp. 516 (16)–530 (26)]. These involve conjunctions <strong>of</strong><br />

conditionals: “If it is A <strong>the</strong>n it is B; ifitisB<strong>the</strong>n it is C.” The inference pattern<br />

arising from <strong>the</strong>se is an amalgam <strong>of</strong> what now goes by <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> “hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogism” and modus ponens: “If it is A <strong>the</strong>n it is B; ifitisB<strong>the</strong>n it is C. It<br />

is A. Therefore it is C.” The work done by (what is now called) hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogism is ra<strong>the</strong>r understated in this arrangement, which seems to present <strong>the</strong><br />

whole inference as just ano<strong>the</strong>r version <strong>of</strong> modus ponens — modus ponens applied<br />

to a conjunction <strong>of</strong> conditionals, instead <strong>of</strong> a single one. In that case <strong>the</strong> mediate<br />

conditional inferences are brought into neat alignment with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, as involving<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own specialized versions <strong>of</strong> modus ponens (and, in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cases,<br />

modus tollens). But this is at <strong>the</strong> expense <strong>of</strong> not fully articulating <strong>the</strong> distinct<br />

presence <strong>of</strong> (what is now called) hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogism. (ii) The list <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogisms is rounded out by considering what now goes by <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> “disjunctive<br />

syllogism.” The corresponding inference patterns are systematically generated, as<br />

above, by listing a full range <strong>of</strong> substitutional forms. Start with “Ei<strong>the</strong>r it is an<br />

A or it is a B,” negate ei<strong>the</strong>r or both disjuncts to produce an additional three<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disjunction, and thus generate four disjunctive forms. The denial <strong>of</strong><br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> first or <strong>the</strong> second disjuncts in each <strong>of</strong> those four disjunctions creates a<br />

distinct inference pattern for asserting <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> remaining disjunct. The<br />

product <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> analysis is <strong>of</strong> course eight such patterns [Abelard, 1970, pp. 531<br />

(33)–532 (21)]. No compounded disjunctive inference patterns are considered.<br />

Summing <strong>the</strong> variant moods arising from conditionals and disjunctions, we get<br />

a substantially sized list, to be sure. But <strong>of</strong> course very little ground is actually<br />

covered in this exercise, which, because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proliferation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> forms considered,<br />

falsely conveys <strong>the</strong> impression that much ground has been covered. The inference<br />

patterns are generated by what are <strong>of</strong>ten negligible variations in <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> applying<br />

negation. And <strong>the</strong>y cannot include larger, more intricately compounded<br />

structures because Abelard’s relevance account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> connectives simply raises<br />

too many difficulties for this. Even one level <strong>of</strong> nesting between hypo<strong>the</strong>ticals<br />

requires invoking a secondary, temporal conditional; and even one level between<br />

disjunctions requires invoking a secondary, predicate disjunction. The result is a<br />

taxinomically-oriented presentation whose taxonomy leaves something to be desired.<br />

If nothing else, <strong>the</strong> above account <strong>of</strong> Abelard’s work on entailment gives <strong>the</strong> lie<br />

to this pre-scholarly story about medieval logic: that it accomplishes very little<br />

in <strong>the</strong> area <strong>of</strong> propositional logic because <strong>of</strong> a lack <strong>of</strong> interest in <strong>the</strong> area, a lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> interest due to <strong>the</strong> period’s preoccupation with Aristotle, who had no interest<br />

in propositional logic at all. Abelard has a great deal <strong>of</strong> interest in <strong>the</strong> area<br />

and accomplishes much. If we take him at his word and view <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

topical <strong>the</strong>ory as a preparation for <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

we can fairly say that about half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dialectica is given over to discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

propositional logic. The limitation in Abelard’s accomplishment here is nei<strong>the</strong>r one<br />

<strong>of</strong> interest nor insight. It lies in a basic heuristic problem for propositional logic

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!