22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Latin Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> to 1100 25<br />

Theodulf’s logical project differs from Alcuin’s in <strong>the</strong> emphasis it places on<br />

argument, and its lack <strong>of</strong> interest in <strong>the</strong> more metaphysically-inclined logic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Categories. I once argued [Marenbon, 1997], using <strong>the</strong> chronology <strong>of</strong> Alcuin’s work<br />

established by his biographer, Donald Bullough [Bullough, 1991, 37; Bullough,<br />

1997, 581-2] that <strong>the</strong> first medieval logician was not Alcuin, but Theodulf. But<br />

it turns out to be more plausible to retain <strong>the</strong> traditional dating <strong>of</strong> Dialectic to<br />

786-90 [Bohn, 2004], and <strong>the</strong>re is evidence, in any case that Theodulf made use<br />

<strong>of</strong> it [Opus Caroli, 1998, 61; English version in Freeman, 2003, 88-9]. Despite <strong>the</strong><br />

difference in <strong>the</strong>ir main aims and interests as logicians, both Alcuin and Theodulf<br />

are alike in attaching logic to <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial policy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Carolingian Empire, as part<br />

<strong>of</strong> a scheme <strong>of</strong> Christian education and <strong>the</strong> defence <strong>of</strong> Christian doctrine. Between<br />

<strong>the</strong>m, Alcuin and Theodulf map out <strong>the</strong> three main ways in which logic would be<br />

valued throughout <strong>the</strong> early medieval ages: as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liberal Arts, <strong>the</strong>mselves<br />

accepted as <strong>the</strong> beginnings <strong>of</strong> an ultimately Christian educational scheme; as a<br />

tool in <strong>the</strong>ology; and as a weapon in <strong>the</strong> fight against heresy.<br />

Theodulf, Alcuin and Alcuin’s pupils<br />

A merging <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> approaches <strong>of</strong> Alcuin and Theodulf may be indicated by <strong>the</strong><br />

contents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earliest surviving logical manuscript, MS Rome, Biblioteca Padri<br />

Maristi, A. II. 1, which belonged to an associate <strong>of</strong> Alcuin’s, Bishop Leidrad, who<br />

died c. 814. Along with <strong>the</strong> Ten Categories, Porphyry’s Isagoge and extracts from<br />

Alcuin’s Dialectic, it includes Boethius’s first commentary on On Interpretation<br />

and Apuleius’s Peri Hermeneias [Delisle, 1896]. The o<strong>the</strong>r piece <strong>of</strong> evidence that<br />

survives about interest in logic at <strong>the</strong> turn <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ninth century very much reflects<br />

Alcuin’s interests, perhaps because it is found in a set <strong>of</strong> passages connected with<br />

his pupil, Candidus Wizo [ed., Marenbon, 1981, 151-66]. The logical pieces are<br />

mostly linked to <strong>the</strong> Ten Categories (I, XIV, XV), though one (XII) takes an<br />

Aristotelian passage from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ologian Claudianus Mamertus, and ano<strong>the</strong>r (XIII)<br />

may be taken from Boethius’s Categories commentary, though it can perhaps be<br />

explained as an elaboration <strong>of</strong> Cassiodorus.<br />

3.2 Eriugena and <strong>the</strong> Ninth Century<br />

([Marenbon, 1981, 67-87])<br />

John Scottus Eriugena, who worked in <strong>the</strong> 850s and 860s at <strong>the</strong> court <strong>of</strong> Charlemagne’s<br />

grandson, Charles <strong>the</strong> Bald, dominates <strong>the</strong> logic, as well as <strong>the</strong> philosophy<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ology, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ninth century. As in all his work, Eriugena’s logic shows a<br />

strange mixture between ideas that fit closely with <strong>the</strong> Latin tradition, and ideas<br />

that are foreign to it, introduced by <strong>the</strong> fact that John learned Greek and was<br />

deeply influenced by Greek Christian Neoplatonism, combined with an intellectual<br />

temperament inclined to take such elements to <strong>the</strong>ir extremes. In order to<br />

appreciate this combination, it is important to place John in <strong>the</strong> context both<br />

<strong>of</strong> his Latin predecessors and contemporaries, and <strong>the</strong> gloss traditions that be-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!