22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 275<br />

by <strong>the</strong> rules from causes, and <strong>the</strong>y do not correspond to any kind <strong>of</strong> global quantificational<br />

import. They are non-parasitic terms that occur inside <strong>of</strong> complex<br />

clauses, or inside <strong>of</strong> complex terms derived from relative clauses. We focus here<br />

on terms that occur within relative clauses.<br />

Can we extend our rules for <strong>the</strong> causes <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> supposition? The rules do not<br />

presently address non-main terms. They do, however, assign modes <strong>of</strong> supposition<br />

to non-main terms which are main terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir local clauses, relative to <strong>the</strong> local<br />

clauses, and <strong>the</strong>y classify <strong>the</strong> complex terms containing <strong>the</strong>m, relative to <strong>the</strong> main<br />

clause. One might hope that <strong>the</strong>se pieces <strong>of</strong> information would combine to tell<br />

us <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> non-main term in <strong>the</strong> whole proposition. For<br />

example, we can indeed predict that if a complex term C which consists <strong>of</strong> a term<br />

modified by a relative clause has determinate supposition in a proposition P, and<br />

if a term E has determinate supposition within <strong>the</strong> clause that forms <strong>the</strong> relative<br />

clause, <strong>the</strong>n E has determinate supposition in P. For example, <strong>the</strong> complex term<br />

‘horse which some donkey sees’ has determinate supposition in:<br />

Some man sees a horse which some donkey sees<br />

And ‘donkey’ has determinate supposition in:<br />

some donkey sees<br />

Therefore, ‘donkey’ has determinate supposition in <strong>the</strong> whole proposition. (It is<br />

easy to check that one may descend to a disjunction, and ascend back from any<br />

disjunct.)<br />

This fact has more application than might be thought. For this result also<br />

applies to constructions generated from relative clauses, constructions such as<br />

adjectives or participles in attributive position. So we can tell instantly e.g. that<br />

‘spotted’ and ‘running’ have <strong>the</strong> same modes as that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> complex term containing<br />

<strong>the</strong>m in:<br />

Some spotted donkey is running<br />

Some running donkey sees a horse<br />

Anything to which our Fronting rule applies automatically falls into this category,<br />

as ‘king’ in‘Some king’s donkey is running’.<br />

An additional rule is this: if a complex term C which consists <strong>of</strong> a term modified<br />

by a relative clause has merely confused supposition in a proposition P, and if<br />

a term E has determinate supposition within <strong>the</strong> clause that forms <strong>the</strong> relative<br />

clause, <strong>the</strong>n E has merely confused supposition in P. For example, <strong>the</strong> complex<br />

term ‘horse which some donkey sees’ has merely confused supposition in:<br />

Every man sees a horse which some donkey sees<br />

And ‘donkey’ has determinate supposition in:<br />

some donkey sees

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!