22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Latin Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> to 1100 3<br />

here are titled, not ‘On <strong>Logic</strong>’ but ‘On Dialectic’, and <strong>the</strong> logicians treated here<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten referred to <strong>the</strong>mselves as ‘dialecticians’ (dialectici) ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘logicians’.<br />

There certainly was a distinction that could be made, and was in some contexts,<br />

between ‘logic’ and ‘dialectic’ in which ‘logic’ stands for <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> demonstrative<br />

reasoning (and so <strong>the</strong> Analytics), and ‘dialectic’ for persuasive reasoning (and so<br />

<strong>the</strong> Topics). Usually, however, in <strong>the</strong> period until 1100, <strong>the</strong> words were used<br />

interchangeably, with ‘dialectic’ as <strong>the</strong> more common, to cover <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

In what follows, I shall speak simply <strong>of</strong> ‘logic’, although <strong>the</strong> word used in <strong>the</strong><br />

sources will <strong>of</strong>ten be dialectica. (For a ra<strong>the</strong>r different view, see [D’On<strong>of</strong>rio, 1986]).<br />

2.1 Before Boethius<br />

The Latin logical works from before Boethius’s time divide into two groups: <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are Cicero’s Topics, Apuleius’s Peri Hermeneias, Marius Victorinus’s On Definition<br />

and Book IV <strong>of</strong> Martianus Capella’s On <strong>the</strong> Marriage <strong>of</strong> Mercury and<br />

Philology, all <strong>of</strong> which have various links with each o<strong>the</strong>r, as will become clear,<br />

although <strong>the</strong>y also, except for Martianus, provide independent glimpses <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

logic. There is also <strong>the</strong> Ten Categories, which unrelated to <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r Latin works.<br />

Cicero ([Huby, 1989; Long, 1995])<br />

The earliest Latin logical text is also treatise in legal rhetoric. Cicero wrote his<br />

Topics (‘Topica’) [Cicero, 1924] in 44 BC, and pr<strong>of</strong>esses that he will explain <strong>the</strong>re<br />

to his friend Trebatius <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Topics. In fact, <strong>the</strong> work reflects<br />

<strong>the</strong> Rhetoric as much as <strong>the</strong> Topics, and probably handbooks <strong>of</strong> rhetorical and<br />

Peripatetic doctrine even more [Long, 1995, 54-7; Stump, 1989, 57-66]. The subject<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics is said to be <strong>the</strong> finding <strong>of</strong> arguments; as his examples show, Cicero<br />

has in mind particularly <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> an orator in <strong>the</strong> courts. The aim <strong>of</strong> argument<br />

is seen in terms <strong>of</strong> its persuasive effect: it convinces someone <strong>of</strong> something that was<br />

in doubt (§ 8). The tools for finding arguments are, as in Aristotle, <strong>the</strong> topics or<br />

loci. But whereas Aristotle’s topics are a proliferation <strong>of</strong> argumentative strategies,<br />

linked to his doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Categories, Cicero’s topics are a short list <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong><br />

relationships, consideration <strong>of</strong> which can help <strong>the</strong> orator to discover an argument.<br />

They include, for instance, genus, species, likeness, cause, effect, comparison. For<br />

instance, if <strong>the</strong> orator needs to show that <strong>the</strong> heir to a dilapidated house is not<br />

bound to repair it, he can argue that <strong>the</strong> case is similar to that <strong>of</strong> an heir to a<br />

slave, who is not bound to replace him if he has died (§15). All <strong>the</strong>se topics and<br />

arguments are intrinsic, but <strong>the</strong> orator can also argue extrinsically, says, Cicero, by<br />

appealing to authority. The importance for logic <strong>of</strong> this very practically-oriented,<br />

rhetorically directed treatise lies in <strong>the</strong> evidence it gives <strong>of</strong> how Aristotle’s <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

<strong>of</strong> topics had been changed in later centuries, and in <strong>the</strong> use that Boethius would<br />

make <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

For historians <strong>of</strong> logic, <strong>the</strong> most important passage in <strong>the</strong> book is where (§§53-<br />

7) Cicero sets out <strong>the</strong> modi dialecticorum — which consist <strong>of</strong> an extended and<br />

slightly mangled list <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Stoic indemonstrables, expressed, not as <strong>the</strong> Stoics did,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!