22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Relational <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Juan Caramuel 647<br />

presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> binary relational statements on <strong>the</strong> levels <strong>of</strong> proposition<br />

(Part I) and argument (Part II). We shall take up <strong>the</strong> matter below in ra<strong>the</strong>r more<br />

detail.<br />

Herculis <strong>Logic</strong>i Labores Tres (“Three Labors <strong>of</strong> Hercules, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>ian”) appears<br />

to be an interesting collection <strong>of</strong> three studies devoted to three logical problems. 8<br />

The first Labor called Nil-negans (“Negating nothing”) reduces <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> valid<br />

modes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syllogism based on <strong>the</strong> reduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> negative copula to <strong>the</strong> negation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate, i.e. term negation. Caramuel appears to have defended this<br />

so-called infinite logic (negated terms are called “infinite”) as part <strong>of</strong> his bachelor<br />

exams in philosophy at Alcalá, early on in his career. 9 The second Labor entitled<br />

Non-omnis (“Not every”) deals with <strong>the</strong> issue that in natural language — Latin<br />

— <strong>the</strong> compound expression non omnis (not every) is equivalent to “some... not...<br />

and some...,” for instance, “not all students smoke” is equivalent to “some students<br />

do not smoke and some do”, ra<strong>the</strong>r than to “some...not...” only, as is <strong>the</strong> purely<br />

logical meaning. It seems that <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural language quantifier<br />

includes something over and above <strong>the</strong> logical one. Caramuel explores this idea<br />

and shows <strong>the</strong> logical properties <strong>of</strong> statements including Latin non omnis: equivalences<br />

and oppositions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se statements as well as valid modes <strong>of</strong> syllogism.<br />

Finally, <strong>the</strong> third Labor under <strong>the</strong> name Contingens (“Contingent”) is a systematic<br />

treatment <strong>of</strong> modal logic. The basic idea is that contingens (contingent) is<br />

not equivalent solely to “possible”, but “possible and possible not”. 10<br />

The second part <strong>of</strong> Rational Theology, Metalogica, or — as <strong>the</strong> full title reads<br />

— Metalogica: Disputationes de <strong>Logic</strong>ae Essentia, Proprietatibus et Operationibus<br />

Continens (“Metalogic Containing Disputations on <strong>the</strong> Essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>, its Properties<br />

and Operations”), ra<strong>the</strong>r than being a work in formal logic, is a set <strong>of</strong><br />

treatises, formally books, in <strong>the</strong> fields <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> logic (Book I), philosophical<br />

logic (Books VII, IX), metaphysics (Books II, III, IV, V, VI, VIII, X)<br />

and informal logic (Book X). The topics covered range from <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> logic,<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> proposition and semantic paradoxes to issues <strong>of</strong> a metaphysical kind<br />

(beings <strong>of</strong> reason, universals, individuation, self-evident principles etc.). The last<br />

book, tenth in number, called De Severa Argumentandi Methodo (“On a Rigorous<br />

Method <strong>of</strong> Argumentation”), is <strong>the</strong> most extensive <strong>of</strong> all. 11 The content ranges<br />

from informal logic to logic applied to specific problems in philosophy and <strong>the</strong>ology.<br />

Why is Metalogic needed, according to Caramuel? He draws a parallel between<br />

logic and music, both directing sound, but for a different purpose. As<br />

<strong>the</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> musical sound, music, needs musical <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

(“metamusic”), 12 so does <strong>the</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> language sound —<br />

logic — need metalogic. One might object that <strong>the</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> production<br />

<strong>of</strong> language sound is grammar, ra<strong>the</strong>r than logic. According to Caramuel, <strong>the</strong> lat-<br />

8Sometimes listed as published independently in 1651, which is doubtful, however.<br />

9Belazzi [1982], p. 17.<br />

10This was by no means obvious at <strong>the</strong> time; cf. [Roncaglia, 2003]. For a detailed treatment<br />

in Caramuel cf. [Dvoˇrák, 2005].<br />

11It appeared as an independent work in 1644.<br />

12Caramuel refers to A. Kircher’s Musurgia universalis and calls it “metamusic”.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!