22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

624 E. Jennifer Ashworth<br />

to this account <strong>the</strong> names ‘Socrates’ and ‘Aristotle’ on <strong>the</strong> one hand and ‘Seine’<br />

and ‘Brownie’ (<strong>the</strong> donkey) on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r have a different status. The former are<br />

more properly singular terms than <strong>the</strong> latter even for those who are acquainted<br />

with all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se individuals through time. Domingo de Soto rejected this consequence,<br />

arguing that horses, trees and even rivers could enjoy a strong enough<br />

identity, by virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> continuity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir forms and functions, to give a basis<br />

for <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> one singular concept through time.<br />

The topics <strong>of</strong> special quantifiers and <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> singular terms soon disappeared<br />

from <strong>the</strong> logical literature, and <strong>the</strong> topic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> significatum <strong>of</strong> propositions ceased<br />

to be a central issue, though it was touched on in later Thomistic accounts <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> judgement. 75 However, ano<strong>the</strong>r topic to which Domingo de Soto<br />

made a very important contribution was longer-lived. This was <strong>the</strong> classification<br />

<strong>of</strong> signs, both linguistic and non-linguistic. In relation to <strong>the</strong> speaker, spoken<br />

words were said to be instrumental signs, because <strong>the</strong>y were used as instruments<br />

<strong>of</strong> communication, and mental terms were said to be formal signs, because <strong>the</strong>y<br />

represented by <strong>the</strong>ir very nature. In relation to <strong>the</strong> things signified, spoken words<br />

were said to be conventional signs, and mental terms were said to be natural<br />

signs, since <strong>the</strong>ir signification did not depend on choice or convention. In <strong>the</strong><br />

various editions <strong>of</strong> his Summulae, Soto asked whe<strong>the</strong>r one should add a category<br />

<strong>of</strong> customary signs, such as napkins on <strong>the</strong> table as a sign <strong>of</strong> lunch. In <strong>the</strong> end<br />

he concluded that <strong>the</strong>se signs were natural, albeit founded on a convention. 76<br />

Soto’s classifications were elaborated by many later authors, including Sebastian<br />

de Couto in <strong>the</strong> Coimbra commentary and John <strong>of</strong> St. Thomas (1589–1644) in<br />

<strong>the</strong> seventeenth century. 77<br />

3 THE NEW TEXTBOOKS<br />

Outside Spain, work in <strong>the</strong> late medieval tradition came to an abrupt halt around<br />

1530. No new independent treatises in <strong>the</strong> medieval style or commentaries on<br />

Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain were written; <strong>the</strong> publication <strong>of</strong> works written during <strong>the</strong> first three<br />

decades <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century ceased, and <strong>the</strong> publication <strong>of</strong> such medieval<br />

authors as Buridan, Heytesbury and Strode also ceased. Only in Spain did authors<br />

75 See Nuchelmans, Late-Scholastic and Humanist Theories <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Proposition.<br />

76 For discussion and references, see E. J. Ashworth, “The Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Signs in Some Early<br />

Sixteenth-Century Spanish <strong>Logic</strong>ians” in Estudios de Historia de la Lógica. Actas del II Simposio<br />

de Historia de la Lógica, ed. Ignacio Angelelli and Angel d’Ors (Pamplona: Ediciones EUNATE,<br />

1990), pp. 13–38; E. J. Ashworth, “Domingo de Soto (1494–1560) and <strong>the</strong> Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Signs”<br />

in De Ortu Grammaticae: Studies in medieval grammar and linguistic <strong>the</strong>ory in memory <strong>of</strong><br />

Jan Pinborg, ed. B. L. Bursill-Hall, Sten Ebbesen and Konrad Koerner (Amsterdam: John<br />

Benjamins, 1990), pp. 35–48.<br />

77 For Sebastian de Couto, see John P. Doyle, trans., The Conimbricenses: Some Questions on<br />

Signs (Milwaukee: Wisconsin: Marquette <strong>University</strong> Press, 2001); for John <strong>of</strong> St. Thomas [John<br />

Poinsot], see John Deely, ed. and trans., Tractatus de Signis: The Semiotic <strong>of</strong> John Poinsot<br />

(Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1985). For some corrections to<br />

Deely’s discussion, see E. J. Ashworth, “The Historical Origins <strong>of</strong> John Poinsot’s Treatise on<br />

Signs”, Semiotica 69 (1988), 129–147.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!