22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 177<br />

case shows up on <strong>the</strong> denoting phrase that binds <strong>the</strong> variable in it; <strong>the</strong> parasitic<br />

term itself is not grammatically affected. For example, in <strong>the</strong> above example, ‘every<br />

donkey’ receives accusative case, while ‘some seeing-y-thing’ is simply nominative.)<br />

Turning ordinary transitive verbs into participles plus copulas maintains <strong>the</strong><br />

principle that a categorical proposition consists <strong>of</strong> terms plus some syncategorematic<br />

signs plus a copula. In this sense, one can maintain that <strong>the</strong> copula is <strong>the</strong><br />

only true verb. However, it does not maintain <strong>the</strong> principle that a categorical<br />

proposition contains two terms, <strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong> predicate. For analyzing a<br />

transitive verb produces a new term. For example, in ‘Every horse a man is seeing’<br />

<strong>the</strong>re are three terms: ‘horse’, ‘man’ and ‘seeing’. This becomes important<br />

when truth conditions are stated for categorical propositions, since <strong>the</strong>y are almost<br />

always stated for propositions with only a subject and a predicate. 26 One might<br />

hope to see truth conditions for a proposition with three terms, or a recursive<br />

specification <strong>of</strong> truth conditions that would extend to more than two terms. So<br />

far as I know, nothing like this appears in any currently edited manuscript. 27<br />

2.4 Using unanalyzed verbs<br />

We have seen how a verb o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> copula can be decomposed into a copula<br />

plus a common term used indefinitely. The idea is neat in <strong>the</strong>ory, and it was <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

used to illustrate <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong>re is only one real verb, <strong>the</strong> copula. However, in<br />

practice, authors tended to treat verbs as if <strong>the</strong>y could be taken to form categorical<br />

propositions without being analyzed into a denoting phrase and a copula. I will<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten follow this practice in quotes and examples.<br />

2.5 Infinitizing Negation and Conversion<br />

In English we have a prefix ‘non’ which goes on <strong>the</strong> front <strong>of</strong> a noun to indicate<br />

things that <strong>the</strong> noun does not apply to, as in ‘Every nonstudent had to pay’. There<br />

is no danger <strong>of</strong> this prefix being confused with <strong>the</strong> negation ‘not’, because <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are spelled differently and do not occur in <strong>the</strong> same places in sentences. In Latin<br />

however (and also in Aristotle’s Greek) <strong>the</strong>se two items were spelled <strong>the</strong> same:<br />

‘non’. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, if this particle occurs in front <strong>of</strong> a noun <strong>the</strong>re is no way to tell<br />

from <strong>the</strong> spelling whe<strong>the</strong>r it is meant to be prefixed to that noun or whe<strong>the</strong>r it<br />

is merely a preceding word. So some effort had to be put into distinguishing <strong>the</strong><br />

readings <strong>of</strong> a sentence such as<br />

Non homo est animal<br />

which is ambiguous between ‘Not: a man is an animal’ and ‘A non-man is an<br />

animal’. Aristotle called a term prefixed with ’non’ an “infinite” term. (He did not<br />

explain <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> ‘infinite’.) Medieval authors called this prefix “infinitizing<br />

negation” and called <strong>the</strong> separate word ‘non’ “negating negation”.<br />

26 Indeed, <strong>the</strong>y tend to be stated only for <strong>the</strong> original four Aristotelian forms.<br />

27 But much work is still undiscovered and/or unedited.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!