22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 475<br />

from anything), and that has led many commentators to believe that <strong>the</strong>se are <strong>the</strong><br />

only kinds <strong>of</strong> material consequences that Ockham recognizes. This matter cannot<br />

be settled at this point, but some have also raised <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that Ockham’s<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> material consequence would go beyond such specific cases (see [Schupp,<br />

1993; Kaufmann, 1993]).<br />

Buridan, by contrast, is crystal clear concerning his distinction between formal<br />

and material consequence. His very terms are: ‘Formal consequence means that<br />

[<strong>the</strong> consequence] holds for all terms, retaining <strong>the</strong> form common to all. Or [...]<br />

a formal consequence is that which, for every proposition similar in form which<br />

might be formed, it would be a good consequence.’ [Buridan, 1976, 22-23]. A<br />

material consequence is one that does not satisfy this criterion but only <strong>the</strong> modal<br />

criterion.<br />

While it is not immediately obvious why Ockham chose this nomenclature for<br />

his distinction 46 , in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> Buridan <strong>the</strong> terminology espouses perfectly <strong>the</strong><br />

traditional Aristotelian notions <strong>of</strong> form and matter: <strong>the</strong> matter <strong>of</strong> a proposition is<br />

defined by its categorematic terms, while its form is defined by its syncategorematic<br />

terms. Thus, a formal consequence is one that holds in virtue <strong>of</strong> its form (<strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> its syncategorematic terms); a material consequence is one that does<br />

not hold in virtue <strong>of</strong> its form alone but also in virtue <strong>of</strong> its matter (<strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

its categorematic terms). Ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>of</strong> describing Buridan’s criterion is with <strong>the</strong><br />

notion <strong>of</strong> substitutivity: a formal consequence is one that holds in all substitutional<br />

instances <strong>of</strong> its categorematic terms.<br />

Buridan’s use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> substitutional criterion is remarkable in that it is immune to<br />

much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> recent criticism against this criterion, most notably in [Etchemendy,<br />

1990]. This is so because <strong>the</strong> substitutional criterion is applied only to consequences<br />

which already satisfy <strong>the</strong> modal criterion <strong>of</strong> incompatibility between <strong>the</strong><br />

truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> premise and <strong>the</strong> falsity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion. Under purely substitutional<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> (logical) consequence, a clearly invalid logical consequence such as ‘Bill<br />

Clinton was a president <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA, thus Bill Clinton was male’ comes out as valid<br />

if ‘Bill Clinton’ is seen as <strong>the</strong> only non-logical term <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequence (as it happens<br />

to be so that, thus far, all presidents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA have been male, and thus all<br />

substitutional instances for ‘Bill Clinton’ will also validate <strong>the</strong> consequent). But<br />

in Buridan’s account, this putative consequence would not be considered as a valid<br />

consequence in <strong>the</strong> first place, since it is not incompatible for somebody to be <strong>the</strong><br />

president <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA and not be a male (in fact this may happen even in <strong>the</strong><br />

foreseeable future); <strong>the</strong>refore, it cannot be a formal consequence because it is not<br />

a consequence to start with. Buridan’s account is best seen as what Shapiro [1998]<br />

has coined <strong>the</strong> ‘hybrid’ notion <strong>of</strong> formal (logical) consequence (which he presents<br />

as <strong>the</strong> most accurate conceptual characterization <strong>of</strong> logical consequence), that is,<br />

46 Ockham’s choice <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term ‘formal consequence’ seems to be related to John Duns Scotus’<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> ‘formal distinction’. Moreover, references to consequentia formalis can be found in<br />

Scotus’ writings, for example in his Quaestiones super libros Elenchorum (p. 77<strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>Vivès<br />

edition <strong>of</strong> Opera Omnia). On <strong>the</strong> relation between Scotus and Ockham on this matter, see<br />

[Martin, 2004].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!