22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 565<br />

<strong>the</strong> Sentences, which he finished c. 1335. 236 The opening question <strong>of</strong> this work<br />

is devoted to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r somebody can be obliged to do something<br />

against his or her conscience. In <strong>the</strong> second article, Roseth first formulates five<br />

general principles or rules which define <strong>the</strong> rationality <strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> norms, and<br />

<strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> article consists <strong>of</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> various objections to <strong>the</strong> rules<br />

<strong>of</strong> rationality. In rules 1 and 2, Roseth defines formal rationality: describing behaviour<br />

in accordance with <strong>the</strong> norms must not yield contradictions, i.e., a person<br />

should not violate a norm by fulfilling a norm in <strong>the</strong> same system <strong>of</strong> norms. New<br />

obligations can be added to a system as rational norms without fur<strong>the</strong>r changes<br />

only if <strong>the</strong>y refer to omissions and commissions which one is permitted to will.<br />

Roseth pays particular attention to this point because he is interested in <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are omissions or commissions which are permitted, although it is not<br />

permitted to will <strong>the</strong>m; as <strong>the</strong>y cannot be legitimately willed, <strong>the</strong>y cannot be<br />

prescribed as such in a rational body <strong>of</strong> norms. Referring to <strong>the</strong> dictates <strong>of</strong> right<br />

reason, Roseth adds to <strong>the</strong> first rule that what is prescribed must be in <strong>the</strong> power<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> agent in such a way that fulfilling <strong>the</strong> obligation does not result in a great<br />

disaster. Rules 3 and 4 are related to <strong>the</strong> Catholic doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> salvation <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> soul. Rule 5 refers to <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> God’s absolute power, through which an<br />

act which cannot be legitimately willed can be changed into an act which can be<br />

legitimately willed. 237<br />

After <strong>the</strong>se general rules, Roseth discusses various possible objections and develops<br />

some philosophical and logical ideas pertaining to norms. The second objection<br />

runs as follows. It is permitted to will to behave in a way which is not meritorious<br />

though <strong>the</strong> order that one should will to behave in a non-meritorious way is not<br />

rational. It is not rational because it could be violated only in a meritorious way.<br />

The first part is proved as follows. If you are sleeping, you do not behave in a<br />

meritorious way. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, you know that this is a good consequence: since<br />

you are permitted to will <strong>the</strong> antecedent, you are permitted to will <strong>the</strong> consequent.<br />

The main point <strong>of</strong> Roseth’s answer to <strong>the</strong> second objection is that it is mistakenly<br />

assumed that if one is permitted to will <strong>the</strong> antecedent <strong>of</strong> a good consequence,<br />

one is also permitted to will <strong>the</strong> consequent:<br />

I accept <strong>the</strong> following consequence: you are sleeping; <strong>the</strong>refore you do<br />

not benefit from an elicited act. But I deny this consequence: this<br />

consequence is good and you know that it is good; <strong>the</strong>refore if you<br />

are permitted to will <strong>the</strong> antecedent, you are permitted to will <strong>the</strong><br />

consequent. This is because <strong>the</strong>re are consequences which are good<br />

236 This work was copied several times during <strong>the</strong> second half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourteenth century and is<br />

preserved to us in eight manuscripts, only three containing <strong>the</strong> complete work. The first article<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book aroused interest as an independent study <strong>of</strong> natural philosophy and was circulated<br />

in several copies. It was printed, toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> second article <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first question, as <strong>the</strong><br />

first question <strong>of</strong> Determinationes magistri Roberti Holcot at Lyon in 1518. The printed version<br />

is abridged and unreliable. The translations below are based on a transcription <strong>of</strong> manuscripts<br />

and quoted from S. Knuuttila and O. Hallamaa, ‘Roger Roseth and Medieval Deontic <strong>Logic</strong>’,<br />

Logique & Analyse 149 (1995), 75-87.<br />

237 These rules are translated in Knuuttila and Hallamaa 1995, 79-83.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!