22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 115<br />

in <strong>the</strong> designated interval (sitting in <strong>the</strong> former case, reading in <strong>the</strong> latter). So<br />

characterized, it becomes a determinate modality.<br />

Abelard considers <strong>the</strong> inferential relations between determinate and simple<br />

modalities. First, determinate possibility implies simple; “It is possible for Socrates<br />

to read while he reads” implies “It is possible for Socrates to read.” But in general<br />

<strong>the</strong> converse implication, that simple possibility implies determinate, does not<br />

hold. And second, simple necessity implies determinate; “It is necessary for me to<br />

read” implies “It is necessary for me to read while I read.” But again, <strong>the</strong> converse<br />

does not in general hold [Abelard, 1958, p. 36 (11–21); Abelard, 2006, 12.73]. The<br />

failure <strong>of</strong> both converses is instructive.<br />

To say it is necessary for me to read while I read is simply to invoke Aristotle’s<br />

principle and note <strong>the</strong> historical irrevocability <strong>of</strong> my reading while I am reading;<br />

for <strong>the</strong> time period designated by <strong>the</strong> clause “while I read” my reading is an<br />

irrevocable fact. But this says nothing about me and my nature. It does not<br />

say that reading is inevitable for me (or that not reading is incompatible with<br />

my nature), which is what it would need to say in order to establish <strong>the</strong> simple<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> my reading. From this follows <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> converse. Determinate<br />

necessity does not imply simple necessity. 60<br />

More complex is <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r converse. Why does simple possibility<br />

fail to imply determinate possibility? This failure is masked in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> internal<br />

determination, where <strong>the</strong> determining verb is <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> main one; “It is<br />

possible for Socrates to read” may well seem to imply “It is possible for Socrates<br />

to read while he reads.” But certain external determinations make <strong>the</strong> failure<br />

obvious. “It is possible for Socrates to sit” does not imply “It is possible for<br />

Socrates to sit while he stands” because <strong>the</strong> determining verb (“stands”) rules<br />

out that <strong>the</strong> property <strong>of</strong> sitting, with which <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> Socrates is admittedly<br />

compatible, can be realized by him at <strong>the</strong> moment when he is standing. The<br />

lesson here is that simple possibility is temporally indefinite, and <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

simple possibility is no guarantee that it will be realized at a given time. The fact<br />

that Socrates is sitting at a given time implies <strong>the</strong> determinate necessity <strong>of</strong> his<br />

doing so <strong>the</strong>n, and also <strong>the</strong> determinate impossibility <strong>of</strong> his not doing so <strong>the</strong>n; this<br />

determinate impossibility holds <strong>the</strong>n even though <strong>the</strong> simple possibility <strong>of</strong> sitting<br />

holds for Socrates at all times <strong>of</strong> his life.<br />

Indeed, as Abelard elsewhere suggests, it is still possible for someone with<br />

maimed hands to box, for an amputee to walk and for a blind person to see.<br />

In each case <strong>the</strong> possibility is understood abstractly in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong><br />

“sits,” differs from <strong>the</strong> main verb, “reads.” In <strong>the</strong> second <strong>the</strong> determining and main verb are <strong>the</strong><br />

same: “reads.” The former is called an “external” determination, <strong>the</strong> latter an “internal” one<br />

[Abelard, 1958, p. 34 (9–12); Abelard, 2006, 12.67].<br />

60 Note that <strong>the</strong>re is an assumption about <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> temporal determining clause in this<br />

argument, that it is to be read in this way: “Socrates possibly (sits while he stands),” not in<br />

this way: “(Socrates possibly sits) while he stands. ” The former represents a modal reading <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> determining clause, <strong>the</strong> latter an associated temporal reading [Abelard, 1958, p. 37 (5–23);<br />

Abelard, 2006, 12.76].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!