22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 237<br />

2 applied to <strong>the</strong> whole proposition. Probably <strong>the</strong> latter is intended, though <strong>the</strong><br />

statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rule seems to require <strong>the</strong> former.<br />

About 3: The rules seem to make <strong>the</strong> predicate term distributive, since both<br />

quantifier signs individually distribute it. This conflicts with <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> criteria. 94<br />

About 5 and 6: The same thing can be said for <strong>the</strong> predicate terms <strong>of</strong> examples<br />

5and6if‘not’ is taken to be a distributing sign when it occurs within a basic<br />

categorical proposition. If on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand <strong>the</strong> ‘not’ has no effect at all, <strong>the</strong><br />

predicate term is clearly distributive because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ’every’ or‘no’. In ei<strong>the</strong>r case<br />

<strong>the</strong> result conflicts with <strong>the</strong> criteria.<br />

So <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory do not hang toge<strong>the</strong>r. If <strong>the</strong> criteria for modes<br />

<strong>of</strong> supposition are accurately stated above, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> rules for causes <strong>of</strong> mode <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition do not work for <strong>the</strong> applications in question. Perhaps that means that<br />

some o<strong>the</strong>r criteria are needed, but it is not clear what <strong>the</strong>y might be.<br />

We have been discussing what happens when we look at nonstandard basic<br />

categorical propositions. There are o<strong>the</strong>r complications as well. If ‘not’ isnot<br />

a distributing sign when it occurs outside <strong>of</strong> a minimal categorical proposition,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it is clear that modes <strong>of</strong> supposition in <strong>the</strong> 13th century <strong>the</strong>ory are not<br />

invariant under logical equivalence. In particular, William’s rules <strong>of</strong> equipollence<br />

change modes <strong>of</strong> distribution. Since ‘no’ is equipollent to ‘not some’, if nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

‘not’ (used outside a basic categorical) nor ‘some’ can distribute, <strong>the</strong>n ‘donkey’<br />

is not distributed in ‘Not some donkey is a stone’, though it is distributed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> equipollent proposition ‘No donkey is a stone’. This is not necessarily an<br />

objection — indeed, it seems like a fairly natural consequence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> local nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> modes in <strong>the</strong> 13th century <strong>the</strong>ory. This is like saying that <strong>the</strong> quantifier in<br />

‘¬∀xF x’ is universal, even though <strong>the</strong> quantifier is not universal in <strong>the</strong> logically<br />

equivalent ‘∃x¬Px’. So with respect to quantificational phenomena, classifying<br />

a term as distributed in <strong>the</strong> early <strong>the</strong>ory is much like classifying a quantifier as<br />

universal. Universal-quantifierhood is not preserved under logical equivalence, nor<br />

is distributive-termhood.<br />

Mobility is different, as is <strong>the</strong> analogue for mobility <strong>of</strong> quantifiers. The universal<br />

quantifier is mobile in ‘∀x¬Fx’ as is <strong>the</strong> existential quantifier in ‘¬∃xF x’; in both<br />

cases <strong>the</strong> quantifier may be instantiated; that is, you get a logical consequence by<br />

erasing <strong>the</strong> quantifier and replacing <strong>the</strong> variable it was binding with a name.<br />

(The 14 th century <strong>the</strong>ory, unlike <strong>the</strong> 13 th century one, makes <strong>the</strong> modes <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition behave logically like mobility.)<br />

94 It was common to handle such cases by giving a rule that states: Whatever immobilizes <strong>the</strong><br />

mobile, mobilizes <strong>the</strong> immobile, and vice versa. In that case, one sign mobilizes <strong>the</strong> word and<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r reverses this. This would make <strong>the</strong> predicate immobile — which is clearly <strong>the</strong> right<br />

result. But <strong>the</strong> rules we are examining are about modes <strong>of</strong> supposition, not about mobility, and<br />

William has no “reversal” principles for those.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!