22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 193<br />

One might naturally dispute <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> words have <strong>the</strong> same definitions<br />

in <strong>the</strong> two cases, but one might also naturally accept this. After all, in order to<br />

know which species is being referred to, all you need to understand is <strong>the</strong> word<br />

with its normal definition. Is this a case in which a word is used in two different<br />

ways but with <strong>the</strong> same definition in each case, or is it a case in which two different<br />

but related definitions are appealed to? Writers took both sides <strong>of</strong> this issue. 43<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> realist picture; a meaningful categorematic word has a form that<br />

it signifies, and it is commonly used to supposit for <strong>the</strong> things that fall under <strong>the</strong><br />

form. There are thus three things prominently associated with a term that it may<br />

be used to supposit for: itself, its signified form, and <strong>the</strong> things falling under <strong>the</strong><br />

form.<br />

Material supposition is <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> supposition a word has when it supposits<br />

for itself or for a related piece <strong>of</strong> language. An example is:<br />

Donkey is bisyllabic<br />

Here on <strong>the</strong> most natural interpretation ‘donkey’ is used with material supposition,<br />

to supposit for tokens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word itself.<br />

Simple supposition is <strong>the</strong> sort appealed to in <strong>the</strong> proposition:<br />

Donkey is a species<br />

On <strong>the</strong> most natural interpretation <strong>of</strong> this proposition, ‘donkey’ is used with simple<br />

supposition, to supposit for <strong>the</strong> form that it signifies; in this case for a species <strong>of</strong><br />

animal.<br />

Personal supposition is <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> supposition a word has when it is used<br />

normally, for <strong>the</strong> things falling under <strong>the</strong> signified form. An example is:<br />

Every donkey is running<br />

On <strong>the</strong> most natural interpretation <strong>of</strong> this sentence, ‘donkey’ is used here with<br />

personal supposition — to supposit for individual donkeys.<br />

Writers point out that <strong>the</strong> terms ‘simple’, ‘material’ and ‘personal’ are technical<br />

terms, whose meanings cannot be gleaned from <strong>the</strong>ir non-technical uses. For<br />

Elizabeth Karger’s unpublished translation <strong>of</strong> Tractatus de Univocatione Monacensis, pp. 333-<br />

51 <strong>of</strong> de Rijk II.2.) In About Univocation we read: “Univocation is [a case<strong>of</strong>] <strong>the</strong> supposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> a name having varied, <strong>the</strong> signification having remained <strong>the</strong> same. (Translation <strong>of</strong> a selection<br />

from Fallacie Parvipontane, pp. 545-609 <strong>of</strong> De Rijk I. Bottom <strong>of</strong> second page <strong>of</strong> translation.)<br />

For discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> historical origin <strong>of</strong> univocation, seeDeRijkLM II.I.XV.1 (492).<br />

43 The author <strong>of</strong> About Univocation gives several arguments in favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> view that univocation<br />

should be grouped with equivocation. The author <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Treatise on Univocation explains<br />

how univocation differs from equivocation: in equivocation <strong>the</strong>re is a change in <strong>the</strong> signification<br />

<strong>of</strong> a word, whereas in univocation <strong>the</strong> signification does not change; only <strong>the</strong> appellation (≈<br />

<strong>the</strong> supposition) changes. Buridan SD 7.3.2 (516) classifies examples <strong>of</strong> univocation as cases <strong>of</strong><br />

equivocation; he defines equivocation in terms <strong>of</strong> a word in context having different significations,<br />

and he holds that in ‘homo ambulat’ <strong>the</strong>word‘homo’ doeshavediversesignificationseven<br />

though <strong>the</strong>re is no new definition. This is because when ‘homo’ is used to stand for <strong>the</strong> species<br />

it is subordinated to a different mental concept than when it is used to stand for persons.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!