22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Paradoxes <strong>of</strong> Self-reference 583<br />

If it is asked whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> predicate <strong>of</strong> this proposition refers to <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

itself, no answer can be given. For if <strong>the</strong> predicate describes <strong>the</strong> whole, <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

must be like it says, that is, a proposition not described by its predicate,<br />

contrary to what was assumed, and if it does not, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is described<br />

by its predicate, contrary to what was assumed. The author claims that<br />

<strong>the</strong> mentioned clause cannot be a predicate in a proposition, and thus <strong>the</strong> considered<br />

sentence-looking piece <strong>of</strong> language lacks a predicate and is not a proposition.<br />

This <strong>of</strong> course solves <strong>the</strong> problem, but leaves one wondering why exactly <strong>the</strong> clause<br />

cannot be a predicate [De Rijk, 1966, 113].<br />

The same arbitrariness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> solution is visible in an even more serious way in<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r example considered by <strong>the</strong> author. Suppose that on an o<strong>the</strong>rwise empty<br />

page, or embedded within a completely true text it reads<br />

A proposition written on this page is false.<br />

The author claims: “it must be said that this proposition cannot be written ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

alone or with truths”. But what does this mean? Does <strong>the</strong> pen stop if one tries<br />

to write something like this? The author seems to go back to something like<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinction between asserting and putting forward discussed above. Literally,<br />

he distinguishes between writing as “drawing figures” (figuras protrahere) andas<br />

“representing figures” (figuras representare). The latter can, <strong>the</strong> author claims,<br />

be cancelled (cassari). Thus, it appears that it is possible to draw on <strong>the</strong> page<br />

something looking exactly like a proposition, but <strong>the</strong> ink will fail to become letters<br />

and words [De Rijk, 1966, 113–114].<br />

The third class <strong>of</strong> insolubles is discussed so shortly that it is impossible to see<br />

what <strong>the</strong> author exactly means. The example is ‘something is not true about<br />

itself’, and <strong>the</strong> idea appears to be that such examples are based on what it is to be<br />

a proposition [De Rijk, 1966, 115]. However, in <strong>the</strong> short discussion <strong>the</strong> example<br />

looks like it would belong toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> former example <strong>of</strong> using ‘proposition<br />

not referred to by its predicate’ as <strong>the</strong> predicate. That example was classified as<br />

a linguistic paradox. In <strong>the</strong> later treatises on insolubles <strong>the</strong> distinction between<br />

insolubles arising from human acts or from linguistic structure seems to remain a<br />

standard classification. The third category seems to disappear, though.<br />

‘THE POSITUM IS FALSE’ AS THE POSITUM<br />

As we noted, <strong>the</strong> author <strong>of</strong> Insolubilia Monacensia discusses <strong>the</strong> paradoxes <strong>of</strong> selfreference<br />

in a distinctively disputational context, where <strong>the</strong> respondent evaluates<br />

sentences put forward by <strong>the</strong> opponent. Also, he shows knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> medieval<br />

disputational technique <strong>of</strong> obligations. However, <strong>the</strong> disputational context plays<br />

no substantial role in his ways <strong>of</strong> setting <strong>the</strong> paradox or his solutions <strong>of</strong> it. In<br />

particular, he does not present <strong>the</strong> paradox as a technical obligation in <strong>the</strong> way<br />

medieval obligational disputations were presented. The medieval logical genres <strong>of</strong><br />

obligations and insolubles thus started as distinct fields. Never<strong>the</strong>less, it seems

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!