22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> at <strong>the</strong> Turn <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Twelfth Century 67<br />

are, <strong>the</strong>n, distant formally from <strong>the</strong> model <strong>of</strong> Boethius, and <strong>the</strong>y are usually distant<br />

in content too, whereas some composite commentaries contain many passages<br />

borrowed from, or closely based on, Boethius. ‘Literal’ and ‘composite’ should not,<br />

however, be thought <strong>of</strong> as designating two completely distinct classes: literal commentaries<br />

contain some more discursive comments, and composite commentaries<br />

can have sections where <strong>the</strong> exegesis is merely literal. There were also ‘problem<br />

commentaries’ (<strong>the</strong> best known is Abelard’s <strong>Logic</strong>a Nostrorum petitioni sociorum),<br />

which concentrated on discussing <strong>the</strong> difficult issues, with very little or no literal<br />

commentary. None <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se has been dated to before c. 1120, but <strong>the</strong>y should be<br />

born in mind, since it will turn out that <strong>the</strong> chronology <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commentaries is far<br />

less fixable than has been believed.<br />

All <strong>the</strong>se commentaries belong to <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> teaching and learning logic in<br />

<strong>the</strong> ca<strong>the</strong>dral schools, and especially in <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>of</strong> Paris, which were beginning<br />

to become important in <strong>the</strong> early twelfth century. But what exactly is <strong>the</strong>ir relation?<br />

Were <strong>the</strong>y drawn up to be read out by <strong>the</strong> master, or are <strong>the</strong>y, ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

lecture-notes taken by students? A few commentaries — notably one on On Interpretation<br />

(H5) — contain passages recording questions, discussion and humorous<br />

(sometimes obscene) asides that appear to be a very direct record <strong>of</strong> what went<br />

on during a particular set <strong>of</strong> lectures [Iwakuma, 1999, 94-7]. O<strong>the</strong>r commentaries<br />

give <strong>the</strong> impression <strong>of</strong> having been more formally written up. Probably <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

a range <strong>of</strong> different relationships between <strong>the</strong> various texts that survive and <strong>the</strong><br />

lectures with which <strong>the</strong>y are connected, and it goes beyond a simple choice between<br />

teacher’s text or lecture notes, since lecture notes might be presented to a<br />

teacher for correction or <strong>the</strong>y might form <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> a student’s own lectures,<br />

with passages revised ands his own particular take on controversial issues added.<br />

These are conjectures, but one thing at least is clear: <strong>the</strong> twelfth-century logical<br />

commentaries were not usually conceived <strong>of</strong> or created as literary works, produced<br />

by a given, single author. They are, for <strong>the</strong> most part at least, records <strong>of</strong> teaching<br />

and learning, in which individual masters’ views on issues may well play an important<br />

role, but which draw <strong>of</strong>ten on many sources. The relations between different<br />

versions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same basic commentary show how freely one master would feel he<br />

could borrow from and adapt <strong>the</strong> teaching <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r: an example is provided<br />

by <strong>the</strong> ‘C8 complex’ (see [Marenbon, 2000+] in <strong>the</strong> revised web-based version <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Categories list). The result is that commentaries have a layered form, with<br />

extra material added, perhaps in a number <strong>of</strong> stages. Where we have manuscripts<br />

<strong>of</strong> different versions, it is easy to see how <strong>the</strong> later versions are layered, with a<br />

stratum that follows <strong>the</strong> earlier commentary, and one or more strata added. For<br />

example, in P3, after a discussion <strong>of</strong> Porphyry’s questions shared by <strong>the</strong> three<br />

manuscripts, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> manuscripts, now in Paris, adds a passage giving an alternative<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phrase ‘only in bare, pure thoughts’, in which it is related<br />

to non-existents, such as chimaeras. If we had only <strong>the</strong> Paris manuscript, it would<br />

not be so clear that this paragraph was an added layer. We should suspect, <strong>the</strong>refore,<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>of</strong>ten layers <strong>of</strong> this sort within commentaries for which only<br />

one manuscript survives, or in <strong>the</strong> earliest version we have <strong>of</strong> a commentary that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!