05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

148<br />

David Sedley<br />

The great bulk of modern studies agree <strong>in</strong> locat<strong>in</strong>g Plato’s formal proof<br />

of the soul’s immortality (or, more strictly, imperishability) <strong>in</strong> what I<br />

have labelled Stage 2. The above analysis locates it squarely <strong>in</strong> Stage<br />

1, <strong>and</strong> treats Stage 2 as a corollary: given that the soul is immortal,<br />

upon the death of the human be<strong>in</strong>g we can <strong>in</strong>fer that it departs from<br />

the body <strong>and</strong> goes to Hades. The corollary need not be read as <strong>in</strong> any<br />

way anticlimactic. That the soul migrates to Hades when death comes<br />

has been central to Socrates’ contentions from the start. The dialogue’s<br />

very first argument for immortality, the Cyclical Argument (69e5–<br />

72d10), was likewise cast as a defence of the Hades mythology.<br />

Hence its confirmation at the very end is no trivial afterthought, but<br />

fundamental to Socrates’ entire argument, as well as effect<strong>in</strong>g a smooth<br />

transition to the conclud<strong>in</strong>g myth, itself centred on the geography of<br />

Hades.<br />

I shall now cut straight to the conclud<strong>in</strong>g moves of Stage 1.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce soul is the essential bearer of life, Socrates ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, it is <strong>in</strong>capable<br />

of admitt<strong>in</strong>g the opposite property, death (105c8-d12) – an <strong>in</strong>capacity<br />

which he elucidates with a comparison to the way <strong>in</strong> which the<br />

number three is <strong>in</strong>capable of evenness (105d13 – 15, recall<strong>in</strong>g 104e5).<br />

There then follows the all-important conclusion (105e2 –10):<br />

‘Well now, what do we call that which does not admit death?’<br />

‘Deathless/immortal (athanaton).’<br />

‘Does soul not admit death?’<br />

‘No.’<br />

‘Then soul is someth<strong>in</strong>g deathless/immortal ()h\matom %qa xuw^)?’<br />

‘It is someth<strong>in</strong>g deathless/immortal.’<br />

‘Well now,’ said Socrates, ‘are we to say that this has been shown/proved<br />

(!podede?whai)? What do you th<strong>in</strong>k?’<br />

‘Yes, <strong>and</strong> most satisfactorily (l\ka ce Rjam_r), 5 Socrates.’<br />

This, the f<strong>in</strong>ale of Stage 1, is as clearly as one could ask flagged up as<br />

conclud<strong>in</strong>g the demonstration of the soul’s immortality. Yet it is hard<br />

to f<strong>in</strong>d an <strong>in</strong>terpreter who recognises it as the conclusion. Why should<br />

this be so?<br />

5 With !podede?whai … l\ka ce Rjam_r, 105e8 – 10, compare Simmias’ acceptance<br />

of the Recollection Argument: 77a5, Rjam_r !pod]deijtai, <strong>and</strong> Rjam_r<br />

ja· aqh_r, used to refer back to that same acceptance at 92e1 – 2. ‘Adequately’<br />

is too weak a translation. If such unwaver<strong>in</strong>g confidence <strong>in</strong> his conclusion goes<br />

beyond the familiar epistemological caution of Plato’s Socrates, that is no doubt<br />

because <strong>in</strong> Plato’s eyes noth<strong>in</strong>g less than total confidence could have led Socrates<br />

to face death as he did.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!