05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Anima Christiana 457<br />

pretty terrible, so that <strong>in</strong> attack<strong>in</strong>g them Tertullian is at least on the right<br />

side of the battle-field. And if his attack is not uniformly successful, he<br />

certa<strong>in</strong>ly l<strong>and</strong>s a few shrewd blows – <strong>and</strong> I confess that I see no reason to<br />

apply the term “sophism” to anyth<strong>in</strong>g he says <strong>in</strong> Chapter 6. For example,<br />

when Tertullian states that “if be<strong>in</strong>g moved by someth<strong>in</strong>g else is<br />

characteristic of body, then how much more is mov<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

else” (6.3), he has been accused of advanc<strong>in</strong>g “an outrageous sophism”<br />

17 . It is the accusation which is outrageous: the sentence does<br />

not express a sophism, nor even a ropy argument, for it doesn’t express<br />

an argument at all. Nor does it express an outrageous falsehood: whether<br />

or not it expresses a truth, it surely expresses someth<strong>in</strong>g which many<br />

people will f<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>in</strong>itially at least, rather plausible.<br />

But if Tertullian rightly rejects the Platonist arguments, <strong>and</strong> rejects<br />

them without fraudulence, he doesn’t deserve much praise for swallow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the Stoic syllogisms <strong>in</strong> favour of corporeality. Take the first of the<br />

four: Zeno, def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the soul as <strong>in</strong>nate spirit, argues thus: “That on<br />

the removal of which an animal dies is a body. When the <strong>in</strong>nate spirit<br />

is removed, the animal dies. Therefore the <strong>in</strong>nate spirit is a body. Therefore<br />

the soul is a body” (5.3). Seneca dismissed th<strong>in</strong>gs of that sort, which<br />

he thought were typical of the early Stoa, as puerile trifles, as <strong>in</strong>eptiae. 18<br />

He meant that they would never persuade anyone of the truth of their<br />

conclusions. I dare say he was right. But that is irrelevant; for the arguments<br />

were surely advanced as proofs of their conclusions – <strong>and</strong> the<br />

question of whether or not they conv<strong>in</strong>ce has noth<strong>in</strong>g to do with<br />

their probative status.<br />

Nonetheless, just as the Stoic syllogisms are not persuasive, so they<br />

are not probative. The four arguments which Tertullian transcribes <strong>and</strong><br />

commends are simply bad arguments. Perhaps a bit of t<strong>in</strong>ker<strong>in</strong>g might<br />

improve them? I doubt it; but <strong>in</strong> any case Tertullian does not t<strong>in</strong>ker,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he was presumably satisfied with them as they are.<br />

After he has applauded the Stoics <strong>and</strong> exploded the Platonists, Tertullian<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ally calls upon Scripture: “As far as the philosophers are concerned,<br />

that is enough, s<strong>in</strong>ce as far as we Christians are concerned it is<br />

superfluous – for us, the corporeality of the soul is evident from the gospels”<br />

(7.1). Half a page, the story of Lazarus, <strong>and</strong> the question is settled.<br />

says of one rather anodyne passage that “that is the fallacy of the excluded middle,<br />

one of Tertullian’s favourites” (1971, 217).<br />

17 Wasz<strong>in</strong>k 1947, 37*.<br />

18 See Barnes 1997, 12 – 20.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!