05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

276<br />

Christopher Shields<br />

P 5 : In the case of soul-body compounds, the entelecheia is the soul.<br />

C 3 : Hence, <strong>in</strong> the case of soul-body compounds, the compound is a unity<br />

by be<strong>in</strong>g suitably related to the soul.<br />

P 4 : If the compound is a unity by be<strong>in</strong>g suitably related to the soul as its<br />

source of unity, then it is not necessary to ask whether the soul <strong>and</strong><br />

body are one.<br />

C: Hence, it is not necessary to ask whether the soul <strong>and</strong> body are one.<br />

There is noth<strong>in</strong>g amiss or confused <strong>in</strong> the question of soul-body unity,<br />

<strong>and</strong> there is no mistake, categorial or otherwise, betrayed <strong>in</strong> its formulation.<br />

It is not necessary to ask the question of whether soul <strong>and</strong> body<br />

are one, for we have its answer available to us.<br />

This answer is given, as this reconstruction makes explicit, <strong>in</strong> terms<br />

of Aristotle’s appeals to homonymy <strong>and</strong> the notion of the soul’s be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

an entelecheia. The <strong>in</strong>terim conclusions simply trace the cha<strong>in</strong> of <strong>in</strong>ferences<br />

upon which the compressed remarks <strong>in</strong> this passage rely. Accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to this responsive <strong>in</strong>terpretation, then, we have no need to ask<br />

whether the soul <strong>and</strong> body are one, because we have our answer at<br />

the ready: the compound is one as a non-core homonym, depend<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

<strong>in</strong> the manner of all non-core homonyms, on its core source, or archÞ,<br />

<strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>stance, the soul, which is its entelecheia.<br />

Of course, a complete appraisal of this argument would require a full<br />

specification of a number of as-yet unexplicated notions, not least the<br />

notion of be<strong>in</strong>g ‘suitably related’ to a core. As I have argued elsewhere,<br />

the relevant notion of suitability is to be given <strong>in</strong> terms of Aristotle’s<br />

four-causal explanatory schema, 17 <strong>and</strong> here we can only observe that<br />

the soul as entelecheia fits that schema precisely, because, as we have<br />

seen Aristotle <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g, it is the formal, f<strong>in</strong>al, <strong>and</strong> efficient cause of<br />

the compound (de An. 415b8 –14; cf. PA 467b12–25; Ph. 255a6 –<br />

10). For present purposes, it matters most that this version of the responsive<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation frankly accepts the soul as prior to the compound <strong>in</strong><br />

terms of unity: it is the unity of the soul, as the entelecheia of the compound<br />

which grounds <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>s the unity of the compound, <strong>and</strong> not<br />

the other way around. The soul is, <strong>in</strong> this respect at least, prior.<br />

17 See Shields 1999, 110 – 122.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!