05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

34<br />

Carl Huffman<br />

of the body, but those arguments would not tell aga<strong>in</strong>st a comm<strong>and</strong>center<br />

psychÞ, which was a harmony of its own physical elements. 34 It<br />

appears, then, that we can assign to Philolaus a view of the soul that allows<br />

us to reconcile what is said about psychÞ <strong>in</strong> fragment 13 with the<br />

doctr<strong>in</strong>e of a soul as a harmony, while still allow<strong>in</strong>g the psychÞ to be a<br />

transmigrat<strong>in</strong>g soul. I now want to go back <strong>and</strong> show that an earlier version<br />

of this conception of soul can be found <strong>in</strong> the testimonia for Pythagoras<br />

himself.<br />

There are three testimonia about Pythagoras’ conception of the soul<br />

dat<strong>in</strong>g to the sixth <strong>and</strong> fifth century. 35 One of these is the passage <strong>in</strong><br />

Herodotus discussed above, <strong>in</strong> which psychÞ seems to refer particularly<br />

to the seat of emotions <strong>and</strong> desires, which transmigrates from body to<br />

body. The unnamed Greeks who, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Herodotus, borrowed<br />

this idea from the Egyptians are likely to <strong>in</strong>clude Pythagoras. That Pythagoras<br />

specifically used the word psychÞ to pick out this conception of<br />

soul is suggested both by his successor Philolaus’ use of the word <strong>in</strong> this<br />

way <strong>and</strong> also by a second testimonium, the oldest testimonium we have, a<br />

famous fragment of Pythagoras’ contemporary, Xenophanes of Colophon.<br />

The fragment does not mention Pythagoras by name, but Diogenes<br />

Laertius (8.36) tells us that he was <strong>in</strong>deed the subject of the<br />

l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> modern scholars have generally agreed. The fragment reads:<br />

“They say that once, when a puppy was be<strong>in</strong>g beaten as he was pass<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

he pitied it <strong>and</strong> spoke the follow<strong>in</strong>g words: ‘stop <strong>and</strong> do not keep hitt<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly the soul (psychÞ) of a friend, which I recognized<br />

when I heard it yelp’.” (Xenophanes, fr. 7) There are obvious perils <strong>in</strong><br />

try<strong>in</strong>g to reconstruct Pythagoras’ conception of the soul from a hostile<br />

presentation of it such as this. Still, Claus goes too far when he argues<br />

that “it is frankly absurd to imag<strong>in</strong>e that we can penetrate [the] satirical<br />

style to f<strong>in</strong>d the actual substance or language of an underly<strong>in</strong>g philosophical<br />

or religious doctr<strong>in</strong>e” 36 . Certa<strong>in</strong>ty cannot be achieved given<br />

such evidence, but some possibilities can be identified, which can<br />

34 Guthrie (1962, 316) views the Pythagorean soul as “a harmony of its own parts”<br />

but for Guthrie its parts are numbers rather than physical elements as I have suggested.<br />

35 Because of the unreliability of the later tradition regard<strong>in</strong>g Pythagoras, it is necessary<br />

to start from evidence that is prior to <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent of the distortions<br />

that first arose <strong>in</strong> the early Academy <strong>and</strong> only admit later evidence to the extent<br />

to which it is of a piece with the early evidence (Burkert 1972).<br />

36 Claus 1981, 5.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!