05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The priority of soul <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s De anima: Mistak<strong>in</strong>g categories? 279<br />

exist without the body (or the compound), then it is not ontologically<br />

prior to the body (or the compound). Hence, the soul is <strong>and</strong> is not ontologically<br />

prior to the body (or the compound). For this problem, it<br />

will not matter which relata we choose.<br />

It is perhaps worth not<strong>in</strong>g at this juncture that this problem, or<br />

seem<strong>in</strong>g problem, is really just the flip-side of Ackrill’s important problem<br />

about the homonymy of the body. 21 That problem, <strong>in</strong> my formulation,<br />

follows from just two theses:<br />

• A General Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Hylomorphism: If m is the matter of a compound<br />

c, <strong>and</strong> f its form, then m is cont<strong>in</strong>gently enformed by f.<br />

• The Homonymy of the <strong>Body</strong>: A body which has lost its soul is not a<br />

body, “except homonymously” (de An. 412b10–27).<br />

With those theses, we can generate an apparent contradiction:<br />

1. If m is the matter of a compound c, <strong>and</strong> f its form, then m is cont<strong>in</strong>gently<br />

enformed by f (The General Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Hylomorphism).<br />

2. A liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g is a compound of form <strong>and</strong> matter: the body is the<br />

matter <strong>and</strong> the soul is the form (de An. 412a19 –22).<br />

3. Hence, <strong>in</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g, the body is cont<strong>in</strong>gently enformed by the<br />

soul (1, 2).<br />

4. A liv<strong>in</strong>g body which has lost its soul is not a body, except homonymously<br />

(de An. 412b10–27).<br />

5. If (4), then the liv<strong>in</strong>g body is not cont<strong>in</strong>gently enformed by the soul.<br />

6. Hence, <strong>in</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g, the body is not cont<strong>in</strong>gently enformed by<br />

the soul (4, 5).<br />

7. Hence, <strong>in</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g, the body both is <strong>and</strong> is not cont<strong>in</strong>gently<br />

enformed by the soul (3, 6).<br />

Ackrill is surely right that there is a prima facie problem here for Aristotle.<br />

What has not always been appreciated is that this problem is really just a<br />

consequence of the priority of the soul. For its key premise, (4) that a<br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g body which has lost its soul is not a body except homonymously,<br />

is a straightforward consequence of Aristotle’s commitment to the priority<br />

of soul over the body. Indeed, one would be hard-pressed to underst<strong>and</strong><br />

why Aristotle would <strong>in</strong>sist on such a claim were it not for his<br />

antecedent commitment to that priority.<br />

If we merge these problems, we see their jo<strong>in</strong>t source. Given the<br />

ontological priority of actuality, the soul is existentially <strong>in</strong>dependent<br />

21 Ackrill 1972/1973, 119–133.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!