05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Anima Christiana 455<br />

the Bible until he has exhausted the reason of the philosophers. In<br />

Chapter 5 he starts the discussion, <strong>in</strong> a curiously oblique manner, by<br />

mention<strong>in</strong>g Plato <strong>and</strong> the Platonists:<br />

Let him summon <strong>in</strong> aid Eubulus (whoever he was), <strong>and</strong> Critolaus, <strong>and</strong><br />

Xenocrates, <strong>and</strong> Aristotle – who on this matter was his friend. Perhaps<br />

there would be more of them concerned to take corporeality away from<br />

the soul had they not seen others – <strong>and</strong> more – on the other side who<br />

claimed a body for the soul. (5.1)<br />

Aga<strong>in</strong>st Plato <strong>and</strong> his little group of supporters, Tertullian draws up a list<br />

of those pagan th<strong>in</strong>kers who had taken the soul to be corporeal (5.2). At<br />

the end of the list, <strong>and</strong> as its chief ornaments, come the Stoics; <strong>and</strong> Tertullian<br />

sets out four of their arguments – one from Zeno, two from<br />

Cleanthes, one from Chrysippus – <strong>in</strong> favour of psychic corporeality<br />

(5.3 –6).<br />

The Stoics are treated by Tertullian with an exceptional civility –<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed, they are treated with respect. 14 He <strong>in</strong>troduces them <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

way: “… but I also <strong>in</strong>voke the Stoics, who called the soul spirit,<br />

very like us (for breath <strong>and</strong> spirit are very close to one another) <strong>and</strong> who<br />

nevertheless would persuade us that the soul is a body” (5.2). In other<br />

words – or so it seems – the Stoics ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> a true theory about the<br />

soul; <strong>and</strong> they support it by conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g arguments. At 2.5, Tertullian<br />

had implied that, at best, the pagans support true theses with bad arguments<br />

or false theses with good arguments; but now it seems that the<br />

Stoics, pagan though they were, offered – <strong>in</strong> one <strong>in</strong>stance at least –<br />

good arguments for a true thesis.<br />

But that is not quite what Tertullian says: the Stoic thesis that soul is<br />

spirit is “very like” the Christian thesis that soul is breath – but it is not<br />

the same thesis. That the soul is breath, or flatus, is proved by the Bible;<br />

for when the Lord God breathed <strong>in</strong>to Adam’s nostrils (Gn 2.7), what he<br />

breathed <strong>in</strong> was, pla<strong>in</strong>ly, a soul. Now “breath <strong>and</strong> spirit are very close to<br />

one another” (<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek their proximity is l<strong>in</strong>guistically evident –<br />

pmo^ <strong>and</strong> pmeOla). But they are not the same th<strong>in</strong>g. Quite the contrary:<br />

when Hermogenes confounded the two, he made a colossal <strong>and</strong> damn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

mistake (11.2), <strong>and</strong> the Stoic thesis that soul is spirit is not a Christian<br />

truth but a heretical falsehood. So here too the pagans are not adduced<br />

with undiluted admiration: they produce good arguments – but for a<br />

false thesis. (“But how can that possibly be? How can you offer a<br />

14 Note also 6.7, where Tertullian commends the Stoic view that the arts are corporeal;<br />

<strong>and</strong> 20.1, the celebrated “Seneca saepe noster”.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!