05.11.2013 Views

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Aristotle on desire <strong>and</strong> action 305<br />

In Aristotle’s view, when desire moves the animal, there is a series of<br />

basic, fully determ<strong>in</strong>ate, psycho-physical processes. One cannot def<strong>in</strong>e<br />

desire simply as a type of heat<strong>in</strong>g of the blood (without reference to<br />

its psychological goal) s<strong>in</strong>ce it is the type of heat<strong>in</strong>g which is directed<br />

towards this goal. Nor can one def<strong>in</strong>e desire solely <strong>in</strong> psychological<br />

terms (as see<strong>in</strong>g A as pleasant) s<strong>in</strong>ce one cannot def<strong>in</strong>e the relevant<br />

type of see<strong>in</strong>g without reference to the heat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> cool<strong>in</strong>g of the<br />

body. Remove that <strong>and</strong> one has not dist<strong>in</strong>guished desir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> (merely)<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that A is pleasant. The psychological <strong>and</strong> physical features can<br />

be thought of as determ<strong>in</strong>ables, requir<strong>in</strong>g additional determ<strong>in</strong>ants to<br />

generate the determ<strong>in</strong>ate phenomenon of desire. Similar remarks<br />

apply to the movements of the connate pneuma <strong>and</strong> the subsequent<br />

movement of the limbs.<br />

6. “Desire moves the animal with a bodily <strong>in</strong>strument.”<br />

In a recent article, Stephen Menn has argued aga<strong>in</strong>st what he describes as<br />

a ‘fashionable’ hylomorphic account of the soul. 14 He notes (correctly)<br />

that Aristotle describes the body as organic: designed to be used as an<br />

<strong>in</strong>strument (organon) for certa<strong>in</strong> purposes. Indeed <strong>in</strong> de An. 433b19<br />

Aristotle talks of desire as “mov<strong>in</strong>g the animal with a bodily <strong>in</strong>strument”.<br />

Thus, for example, the connate pneuma is designed to move the<br />

animal <strong>in</strong> the way required to achieve what the agent desires. In this<br />

way, the connate pneuma is the <strong>in</strong>strument by which desire sets the animal<br />

<strong>in</strong> motion. If one th<strong>in</strong>ks of desire as a passion of the soul, one might say<br />

that (<strong>in</strong> this case) the connate pneuma is the <strong>in</strong>strument by which the soul<br />

sets the animal <strong>in</strong> motion.<br />

When desire moves the body with an <strong>in</strong>strument, it does so because<br />

(or so I have argued) it is an <strong>in</strong>extricably psycho-physical (hylomorphic)<br />

process, the realization of an essentially hylomorphic capacity to desire.<br />

Thus, for example, <strong>in</strong> the case of anger, the desire for revenge is a specific<br />

type of boil<strong>in</strong>g of the blood around the heart which moves the<br />

pneuma <strong>and</strong> so sets the animal <strong>in</strong> action. Although the bodily <strong>in</strong>struments<br />

by which desire moves the animal are dist<strong>in</strong>ct from desire, this does not<br />

mean that desire itself is not a type of bodily process. Indeed, it has to be<br />

a psycho-physical process (a type of bodily process) if it is to move the<br />

connate pneuma <strong>in</strong> the way it does. If desire is a passion of the soul, the<br />

14 2002.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!