04.02.2013 Views

GUIDE TO THE PHILOSOPHY 1938 - 1947.pdf - Rare Books at ...

GUIDE TO THE PHILOSOPHY 1938 - 1947.pdf - Rare Books at ...

GUIDE TO THE PHILOSOPHY 1938 - 1947.pdf - Rare Books at ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

334<br />

ETHICS<br />

as simple and as pleasant as th<strong>at</strong>. There must, one regretfully<br />

concludes, be something wrong with a theory which<br />

always identifies wh<strong>at</strong> one wants to do with wh<strong>at</strong> one<br />

ought to do. It was the difficulty presented by the over-<br />

simplicity of Bentham's view which J. S. Mill (1806-1873)<br />

set himself to meet. His solution is curious. Mill, like<br />

Bentham, officially holds position (A). Mill was, however, an<br />

an intense<br />

exceedingly public-spirited man, imbued by<br />

dislike of wh<strong>at</strong> he calls the selfish egoist "devoid of every<br />

feeling or care but those th<strong>at</strong> centre in his own miserable<br />

individuality". It is, therefore, a m<strong>at</strong>ter of prime import-<br />

.ance for Mill to defend Utilitarianism from the charge<br />

of selfish Egoism, and to prove th<strong>at</strong> the good utilitarian,<br />

no less than the good intuitionist, is required to aim <strong>at</strong><br />

the welfare ofothers. If, then, he can show th<strong>at</strong> the gre<strong>at</strong>est<br />

happiness of the gre<strong>at</strong>est number is the one supreme<br />

good, it will, it is obvious, be the duty of the good utilitarian<br />

to try to promote it. He <strong>at</strong>tempts to do so as follows.<br />

"No reason," he says, "can be given why the general<br />

happiness is desirable, except th<strong>at</strong> each person, so far as<br />

he believes it to be <strong>at</strong>tainable, desires his own happiness.<br />

This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the<br />

proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible<br />

to require, th<strong>at</strong> happiness is a good: th<strong>at</strong> each person's<br />

happiness is a good to th<strong>at</strong> person, and the general happi-<br />

ness, therefore, a good to die aggreg<strong>at</strong>e of all persons."<br />

The argument is a bad one. Wh<strong>at</strong> Mill is, in effect,<br />

saying is th<strong>at</strong>, if A's pleasure is a good to him, B's pleasure<br />

a good to him and C's pleasure a good to him, ami so on,<br />

then the aggreg<strong>at</strong>e pleasures of A, B and C will be good<br />

to all three of them taken together. Therefore, they will<br />

be a good to each one taken separ<strong>at</strong>ely.<br />

But the pleasures ofA, Band G are no more to be moulded<br />

into a single whole than are their persons. Nor is it clear<br />

why, even if they could be so moulded, the resultant<br />

pleasure aggreg<strong>at</strong>e should, on the basis of Mill's hedonist<br />

premises, appear desirable to any of them singly. The<br />

point is obvious enough, and it was obvious, to many

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!